- Library Home /
- Search Collections /
- Open Collections /
- Browse Collections /
- UBC Theses and Dissertations /
- Constructive skepticism, critical thinking and the...
Open Collections
UBC Theses and Dissertations
UBC Theses and Dissertations
Constructive skepticism, critical thinking and the ethics of belief Rebman, John L.
Abstract
One of the primary aims of education is to enable students to secure reliable standards and procedures by which they can acquire beliefs that are, if not true, at least likely to be true. The questions of belief acquisition and the manner in which those beliefs are held, although epistemic, are also distinctively ethical. Implicit within epistemological concepts such as truth, justification and objectivity are ethical concerns such as honesty, integrity and responsibility. In response to the question “What ought I to believe?”, any serious critical thinker must examine the reasons for holding (or not holding) a belief, and ascertain whether or not they are good reasons. Good reasons involve attention to rational or intellectual standards such as evidential support, objectivity, justification and truth. My discussion of the moral dimensions of epistemological questions will follow the path delineated by W.K. Clifford (1877) in his essay “The Ethics of Belief”. Within the context of the notions of intellectual virtues and vices, I will argue that intellectual integrity and epistemic responsibility entail the acceptance of the aforementioned standards and an avoidance of credulity. Recently, however, the Enlightenment project of rationality has come under serious attack from feminist philosophers, neo pragmatists, post-modernist philosophers and proponents of the “sociology of knowledge” who, in their efforts to avoid dogmatism, claim that knowledge lacks foundations, truth is relative to culture or “conceptual scheme,” and objectivity a myth. Although a thorough treatment and discussion of the views advanced by these groups far exceeds the scope of this thesis, their claims are, I shall argue, self-refuting and entail a destructive relativism and possible descent into radical skepticism. For the most part, I will focus my criticisms on Pragmatism, particularly the variety espoused by Richard Rorty, arguably the most influential contemporary philosopher. If the extremes of radical skepticism and dogmatism are to be averted, educators must adopt the premise that knowledge is possible but at the same time accept the fact that much of what we claim to know is uncertain. Hence, many of our beliefs should be regarded as transitory and, therefore, held tentatively. I shall argue that by assuming a posture of humility in the face of knowledge claims, holding to a realist and fallibilist theory of knowledge, entertaining beliefs with a healthy skepticism and abandoning the “quest for certainty” (as Dewey has asserted), we can avoid dogmatism, indoctrination and the intellectual vice of credulity. If we value autonomous critical thinkers as an important component within a liberal democratic society, then these dispositions ought to be fostered in our students. This dispositional approach to critical thinking I refer to as constructive skepticism and will argue that it is a necessary requirement for any serious critical inquirer.
Item Metadata
Title |
Constructive skepticism, critical thinking and the ethics of belief
|
Creator | |
Publisher |
University of British Columbia
|
Date Issued |
1994
|
Description |
One of the primary aims of education is to enable students to
secure reliable standards and procedures by which they can acquire
beliefs that are, if not true, at least likely to be true. The
questions of belief acquisition and the manner in which those
beliefs are held, although epistemic, are also distinctively ethical. Implicit within epistemological concepts such as truth, justification and objectivity are ethical concerns such as honesty,
integrity and responsibility. In response to the question “What
ought I to believe?”, any serious critical thinker must examine the
reasons for holding (or not holding) a belief, and ascertain
whether or not they are good reasons. Good reasons involve attention to rational or intellectual standards such as evidential
support, objectivity, justification and truth. My discussion of the
moral dimensions of epistemological questions will follow the path
delineated by W.K. Clifford (1877) in his essay “The Ethics of
Belief”. Within the context of the notions of intellectual virtues
and vices, I will argue that intellectual integrity and epistemic
responsibility entail the acceptance of the aforementioned standards and an avoidance of credulity.
Recently, however, the Enlightenment project of rationality
has come under serious attack from feminist philosophers, neo
pragmatists, post-modernist philosophers and proponents of the
“sociology of knowledge” who, in their efforts to avoid dogmatism,
claim that knowledge lacks foundations, truth is relative to culture or “conceptual scheme,” and objectivity a myth. Although a
thorough treatment and discussion of the views advanced by these
groups far exceeds the scope of this thesis, their claims are, I shall argue, self-refuting and entail a destructive relativism and
possible descent into radical skepticism. For the most part, I will
focus my criticisms on Pragmatism, particularly the variety
espoused by Richard Rorty, arguably the most influential contemporary philosopher.
If the extremes of radical skepticism and dogmatism are to be
averted, educators must adopt the premise that knowledge is possible but at the same time accept the fact that much of what we
claim to know is uncertain. Hence, many of our beliefs should be
regarded as transitory and, therefore, held tentatively. I shall
argue that by assuming a posture of humility in the face of knowledge claims, holding to a realist and fallibilist theory of knowledge, entertaining beliefs with a healthy skepticism and abandoning
the “quest for certainty” (as Dewey has asserted), we can avoid
dogmatism, indoctrination and the intellectual vice of credulity.
If we value autonomous critical thinkers as an important component
within a liberal democratic society, then these dispositions ought
to be fostered in our students. This dispositional approach to
critical thinking I refer to as constructive skepticism and will
argue that it is a necessary requirement for any serious critical
inquirer.
|
Extent |
2874116 bytes
|
Genre | |
Type | |
File Format |
application/pdf
|
Language |
eng
|
Date Available |
2009-02-24
|
Provider |
Vancouver : University of British Columbia Library
|
Rights |
For non-commercial purposes only, such as research, private study and education. Additional conditions apply, see Terms of Use https://open.library.ubc.ca/terms_of_use.
|
DOI |
10.14288/1.0055507
|
URI | |
Degree | |
Program | |
Affiliation | |
Degree Grantor |
University of British Columbia
|
Graduation Date |
1994-05
|
Campus | |
Scholarly Level |
Graduate
|
Aggregated Source Repository |
DSpace
|
Item Media
Item Citations and Data
Rights
For non-commercial purposes only, such as research, private study and education. Additional conditions apply, see Terms of Use https://open.library.ubc.ca/terms_of_use.