"Arts, Faculty of"@en . "Asian Studies, Department of"@en . "DSpace"@en . "UBCV"@en . "Chen, Chung Kuang Allen"@en . "2012-12-05T20:44:43Z"@en . "2012"@en . "Master of Arts - MA"@en . "University of British Columbia"@en . "The purpose of this thesis is to investigate how contemporary scholarship interpreted sage-kings (\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B) narratives, commonly used in Warring States and Chinese philosophical texts to represent particular visions of ideal rulership, in their understanding of the historical and political contexts of the development of early Chinese intellectual history. Another aim is to find out how these narratives changed over time, and how they revealed the different political concerns of the Warring States philosophers. This project uses a primarily historiographical approach and first surveyed the works of leading scholarship in the field that discusses the use of the sage-kings. Then, two particular narratives are examined in order to demonstrate their evolution over time. The first of these sage-king narratives was on the taming of the great flood by Yu \u00E7\u00A6\u00B9 and the rise of human civilization; the second was on the abdication of Yao \u00E5\u00A0\u00AF to Shun \u00E8\u0088\u009C and the issue of legitimacy in the transfer of political authority. The results of the study shows that even though contemporary scholarship recognizes the importance of the sage-king narratives in understanding political concerns in the history of early China, and the evolution of these narratives over time, there is no consensus in the methodology best used to systematically integrate them. This thesis also concludes that that the sage-kings were used not just as political ideals by texts like the Analects, the Mozi, the Mencius, and the Xunzi, but were also often consciously constructed by the authors of these texts to fulfill this precise role. Furthermore, the results indicate that the sage-kings were also used as counter-narratives by the Zhuangzi and the Hanfeizi, as a way to criticize and undermine those texts that were proponents of the sage-kings. The principal conclusion of this thesis is that sage-kings narratives are more complex and multifaceted than previously thought and deserve a more nuanced and historically aware analysis in future research."@en . "https://circle.library.ubc.ca/rest/handle/2429/43654?expand=metadata"@en . " DEVELOPMENT OF THE SAGE-KING NARRATIVES: IDEALIZED CONCEPTS OF RULERSHIP IN WARRING STATES CHINESE THOUGHT by CHUNG KUANG ALLEN CHEN B.A., The University of British Columbia, 2009 A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS in THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES (Asian Studies) THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA (Vancouver) December 2012 \u00C2\u00A9 Chung Kuang Allen Chen, 2012 ii Abstract The purpose of this thesis is to investigate how contemporary scholarship interpreted sage-kings (\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B) narratives, commonly used in Warring States and Chinese philosophical texts to represent particular visions of ideal rulership, in their understanding of the historical and political contexts of the development of early Chinese intellectual history. Another aim is to find out how these narratives changed over time, and how they revealed the different political concerns of the Warring States philosophers. This project uses a primarily historiographical approach and first surveyed the works of leading scholarship in the field that discusses the use of the sage-kings. Then, two particular narratives are examined in order to demonstrate their evolution over time. The first of these sage-king narratives was on the taming of the great flood by Yu\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9 and the rise of human civilization; the second was on the abdication of Yao \u00E5\u00A0\u00AF to Shun \u00E8\u0088\u009C and the issue of legitimacy in the transfer of political authority. The results of the study shows that even though contemporary scholarship recognizes the importance of the sage-king narratives in understanding political concerns in the history of early China, and the evolution of these narratives over time, there is no consensus in the methodology best used to systematically integrate them. This thesis also concludes that that the sage-kings were used not just as political ideals by texts like the Analects, the Mozi, the Mencius, and the Xunzi, but were also often consciously constructed by the authors of these texts to fulfill this precise role. Furthermore, the results indicate that the sage-kings were also used as counter-narratives by the Zhuangzi and the Hanfeizi, as a way to criticize and undermine those texts that were proponents of the sage-kings. The principal conclusion of this thesis is that sage-kings narratives are more complex and multifaceted than previously thought and deserve a more nuanced and historically aware analysis in future research. iii Table of Contents Abstract .............................................................................................................................. ii Table of Contents .............................................................................................................. ii Acknowledgements .......................................................................................................... iv Dedication ...........................................................................................................................v 1. Introduction ................................................................................................................1 1.1 Warring States Realities ....................................................................................... 3 1.2 Sage-Kings ........................................................................................................... 6 1.3 Statement of Research Questions ....................................................................... 11 1.4 Methodological Matters ..................................................................................... 13 2. Sage-King Narratives: A Contemporary Tale .......................................................15 2.1 Myth, Shamanism, and Sage-King Narratives ................................................... 15 2.2 Sage-Kings and the Philosophical Masters ........................................................ 21 2.3 Late Warring States Critiques of Sage-Kings .................................................... 29 2.4 Sage-Kings as Conscious Fabrications .............................................................. 39 3. Sage-King Narratives and Political Concerns: Two Cases ...................................44 3.1 Flood Taming Narratives of Yu and Human Civilization .................................. 45 3.2 Yao and Shun: Narratives of Rightful Succession or Usurpation ...................... 54 4. Conclusion .................................................................................................................62 5. Bibliography ..............................................................................................................65 iv Acknowledgements I am grateful for the guidance of Dr. Edward Slingerland, my advisor, who inspired me to study the history and philosophy of early China. I would also like to thank the members of my committee, Dr. Chen Jinhua, Dr. Li Duanduan, and especially Dr. Stefania Burk, for their support. I would equally like to thank Dr. Robin Yates for his unwavering encouragements, Dr. Christopher Friedrichs for showing me the meaning of being a great teacher, as well as Dr. Arlene Sindelar for inciting my love of legal history. I am especially grateful to Abraham de Jesus, Clayton Ashton, and Jennifer Lundin Ritchie, for being there with me every step of the way. Without whose friendship, encouragement, support, and guidance, I would not have survived my graduate studies thus far. Also, thank you Chris Lovins for the concern for my humanity and for helpful suggestions on the final drafts of this thesis. Similarly, I would like to recognize my soulmates Allie Slemon and H\u00C3\u00A9l\u00C3\u00A8ne Frohard-Dourlent, whose loving companionship completes me. Thank you to Christine Peralta and Katie Hollet whose camaraderie and mutual encouragement made my entire MA program, especially during the thesis writing process, endurable. My sincere appreciation goes to all my friends, especially those who gave feedback on my research, notably: Mitch Schroeder, Kendall Moraski, Krystin Parkinson, Keltie McLaren, Ramsay Malange, Crystal Hon, Michael Leung, Wenyi Huang, Claire Deng, Dan Shultz, Anne- Sophie Pratte, Sun Nee Tan, and Wayne Kreger. A most heartfelt thank you to: Rachel Freeman, who is my rock; Ines Doli\u00C4\u0087, for being the voice of reason in my life; and Nicolas B\u00C3\u00A9rub\u00C3\u00A9, for believing in me, especially when I no longer did. Finally, and most importantly, thank you to my family for always supporting everything that I have ever endeavoured to accomplish. Without their love, not only would this project not have been possible, but I also would not be the person that I am today. Especially, I want to thank my mother for being the one guiding light in my life, for always listening to me, for always believing in me, and for always reminding me that the most important thing in life is to love what I do. v Dedication \u00E8\u00AA\u00B0\u00E8\u00A8\u0080\u00E5\u00AF\u00B8\u00E8\u008D\u0089\u00E5\u00BF\u0083\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u00A0\u00B1\u00E5\u00BE\u0097\u00E4\u00B8\u0089\u00E6\u0098\u00A5\u00E6\u009A\u0089\u00E3\u0080\u0082 To my parents. 1 1. Introduction One of the most momentous turning points in early Chinese history was the creation of the first imperial state under the Qin \u00E7\u00A7\u00A6 in 221 BCE, which came at the end of the Warring States \u00E6\u0088\u00B0\u00E5\u009C\u008B period (c. fifth century\u00E2\u0080\u0093221 BCE).1 Without exaggeration, one can say that Warring States history is one of the most popular research topics in Sinology, not least because of the wealth of extant textual sources that have survived into modern times, but also because of the nature of the fundamental changes that took place with respect to social organization, political structures, and especially philosophical ideas. As Yuri Pines points out, the Qin conquest and subsequent unification of China was a definitive realization of a vision held by many Warring States authors, who propagated their political ideals and sought to return All-under-Heaven \u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B to what they believed to be an idealized golden age, based on visions of the past, and whose intellectual legacies are the numerous philosophical texts that are extant to this day. 2 The vibrant literary and philosophical culture of the Warring States period would come to influence the development of the burgeoning imperial states of Qin (221\u00E2\u0080\u0093202 BCE) and Han \u00E6\u00BC\u00A2 (206 BCE\u00E2\u0080\u0093220 CE). This rich ideological heritage also, as Pines posits, was a significant contributing factor in the longevity of the Chinese imperial political culture. 3 Recent discoveries of many archaeological manuscripts that can be dated to this very formative period in Chinese history, however, have begun to force many sinologists 1 For the sake of clarity and consistency, I will use the Hanyu Pinyin \u00E6\u00BC\u00A2\u00E8\u00AA\u009E\u00E6\u008B\u00BC\u00E9\u009F\u00B3 for all romanizations of Chinese words and characters in my thesis. In cases where the original translations by other authors were in Wade-Giles, I will change them into pinyin with brackets to indicate the change. 2 Yuri Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire: Chinese Political Thought of the Warring States Era (Honolulu: University of Hawai\u00E2\u0080\u0099i Press, 2009), 2. 3 Ibid., 222. 2 to question and reassess some of their most fundamental conceptions about the political and philosophical realities that have come to be accepted as facts. For example, some have come to question the idea that the so-called Hundred Schools of Thought contended against one another in the Warring States intellectual landscape, where each of these texts represented coherent philosophical lineages based around a robust master\u00E2\u0080\u0093disciple relationship. 4 These discoveries have led Michael Nylan and Michael Loewe to argue in China\u00E2\u0080\u0099s Early Empires: A Reappraisal that \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe study of the early empires in China is itself at a crossroads, one wherein the old paradigms that ruled scholarship in the last fifty years of the twentieth century have given way\u00E2\u0080\u00A6to new hypotheses.\u00E2\u0080\u009D5 Their observations \u00E2\u0080\u009Chave caused us to rethink many of the old divisions between religion, literature, and philosophy\u00E2\u0080\u009D and reveal that there is much debate among academics with regards to how these newly discovered materials have contributed to our understanding of early Chinese history. 6 Major breakthroughs in the study of early Chinese history and philosophy have been possible in part due to the insights offered by these manuscripts, even with some of the inherent philological difficulties working with archaeological texts. Even though some scholars have claimed that these archaeological manuscripts are somehow \u00E2\u0080\u0098better\u00E2\u0080\u0099 or more \u00E2\u0080\u0098authentic\u00E2\u0080\u0099 than the extant received texts, as Enno Giele has pointed out, however, the \u00E2\u0080\u009Cvalue [of the archaeological manuscripts] depends on the questions one 4 Mark Csikszentmihalyi and Michael Nylan, \u00E2\u0080\u009CConstructing Lineages and Inventing Traditions through Exemplary Figures in Early China,\u00E2\u0080\u009D T\u00E2\u0080\u0099oung Pao, Second Series 89 (2003): 99. 5 Michael Nylan and Michael Loewe, eds., China\u00E2\u0080\u0099s Early Empires: A Reappraisal (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 2. 6 Ibid., 4. 3 asks of them and on how the texts, whether excavated or received, are put into context.\u00E2\u0080\u009D7 In order to effectively carry out this kind of research the archaeological context itself is the most important, not only to date the manuscripts themselves, but also offer a more comprehensively contextualized understanding of the history of textual transmission. 8 Within the limited scope of this thesis, however, it is not possible to fully extrapolate and effectively analyze the important contributions of these archaeological manuscripts. Instead, it is my primary goal to revisit a major theme recurrent in the development of Warring States intellectual history, namely, idealized concepts of rulership and governance as embodied by mythical figures known as the sage-kings \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B. I address not only their philosophical significance within the context of the textual sources in which they appear, but I deal with them also in an attempt to understand and analyze how they were used by the authors as a means to assert the superiority of those authors\u00E2\u0080\u0099 own political visions over that of others. 1.1 Warring States Realities In order to better contextualize this entire discussion, it is important first to understand some of the underlying circumstances that characterized the Warring States period in China. When the Zhou \u00E5\u0091\u00A8 Dynasty (1046\u00E2\u0080\u0093256 BCE) ultimately supplanted its predecessor dynasty, the Shang \u00E5\u0095\u0086 (1600\u00E2\u0080\u00931046 BCE), its members justified their conquest and legitimized their political claims to be rulers through what they claimed to 7 Enno Giele, \u00E2\u0080\u009CExcavated Manuscripts: Context and Methodology\u00E2\u0080\u009D in Early Chinese Empires: A Reappraisal, eds. Michael Nylan and Michael Loewe (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010), 114. 8 Ibid. 4 be the Mandate of Heaven \u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E5\u0091\u00BD.9 It was also claimed that the moral character and virtuous behaviours of the Zhou kings garnered their lineage the right to rule All-under- Heaven, and that the overthrowing of the Shang was due to its moral deviance and oppressive rule. 10 The use of these kinds of foundation myths functioned both as political justification and as their claim to legitimacy. Similarly, the first Zhou kings, Wen \u00E6\u0096\u0087 and Wu \u00E6\u00AD\u00A6, were idealized as rulers who restored political order, one sanctioned by Heaven, to an otherwise disorderly world. The Zhou political order was maintained for several generations, but gradually declined through the Spring and Autumn \u00E6\u0098\u00A5\u00E7\u00A7\u008B (c. eighth to fifth centuries BCE), and especially during the Warring States periods. This was caused by critical challenges such as inept rulers, political struggles, and its loss of a means to effectively field military forces to counter the rise of the power of regional lords led to the decline of the Zhou royal house. 11 Associated with this decline was the gradual erosion of the elaborate religious and ritualistic hierarchy that had the Zhou kings themselves at its pinnacle. As Mark Edward Lewis points out, the Warring States period was so named because it was characterized by intense competition and warfare between increasingly powerful states through the \u00E2\u0080\u009Cprogressive extension of military service, and the registration and mobilization of their population.\u00E2\u0080\u009D12 During this period, the Zhou kings still held the title of Son of Heaven \u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E5\u00AD\u0090, and they were at least nominally sovereign over the rulers of the individual warring states; however, in all practicality, 9 K. C. Chang, \"Sandai Archaeology and the Formation of States in Ancient China: Processual Aspects of the Origins of Chinese Civilization,\" in The Origins of Chinese Civilization, ed. David Keightley (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983), 496. 10 Edward L. Shaughnessy, \"Western Zhou History,\" in The Cambridge History of Ancient China, ed. Michael Loewe and Edward Shaughnessy (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999), 292. 11 Ibid., 328\u00E2\u0080\u0093331. 12 Mark Edward Lewis, Sanctioned Violence in Early China (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1990), 53. 5 they themselves were not only powerless to assert the royal ritual prerogatives long usurped by their nominal vassals, but they were also often hostages to the most powerful hegemons who had the military might to dominate the political landscape. 13 This definitive decline and eventual end of the royal lineage was associated with the breaking down of the ritualistic political power wielded by the Zhou kings, while the regional lords began usurping the ritual practices that only the Zhou kings, as Sons of Heaven, were entitled to. This kind of disregard towards the royal house seems merely a minute detail in the grander scheme of Warring States conflicts; nevertheless, it highlights some fundamental transformations in the Zhou political order. The fact was that the Zhou kings could no longer assert their authority, as they did not have effective power to curb the ebbing of their influence over the various regional lords. This attempt to dispense with ritual propriety on the part of the regional aristocracy is precisely the kind of thing that Confucius lamented in one of the chapters in the Analects \u00E8\u00AB\u0096\u00E8\u00AA\u009E. Upon hearing that the Ji \u00E5\u00AD\u00A3 family in the state of Lu \u00E9\u00AD\u00AF had eight rows of dancers performing at a ritual, Confucius lamented, \u00E2\u0080\u009CIf they can condone this, what are they not capable of?\u00E2\u0080\u009D14 This should be interpreted within the context where social rank, and the political power and legitimacy attributed to that status, were intricately associated with ritualistic practices. This example might seem to be a mere oversight, but to Confucius, it was nevertheless a clear offence against the Zhou royal house, the only ones entitled to this particular honour, and also an offence against what he perceived to be appropriate. This kind of sidestepping of the Zhou was symptomatic of the political 13 Shaughnessy, \"Western Zhou History,\" 342\u00E2\u0080\u0093351. 14 Confucius Analects with Selections from Traditional Commentaries, 3.1, trans. Edward Slingerland (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 2003), 17. 6 realities of the era, and it was associated with the disintegration of political order and, by extension, with a descent of All-under-Heaven into chaos and destruction \u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E5\u00A4\u00A7\u00E4\u00BA\u0082. On a more concrete level, the effective decline of Zhou royal authority allowed for regional rulers to compete with one another not only in terms of ritual and political wrangling, but also encouraged \u00E2\u0080\u009Cconstant wars of the\u00E2\u0080\u00A6noble lineages [that] gradually led to the creation of ever larger territorial units through the conquest of alien states and the extension of central government control into the countryside.\u00E2\u0080\u009D15 These centralizing and bureaucratizing states sought to overcome their political rivals by resorting to more aggressive and violent policies of domination, both of their rivals and of their own populace. 16 Ritual propriety and the idea that warfare ought to be sanctioned by Heaven via the Zhou kings became less important in amassing political authority; it was now more closely associated with the ability of the rulers to exert military control over their territory and to use violence to further their political aims. The most significant development that dominated this period was the rise of a new social structure based on this increasingly authoritarian and hierarchical relationship between the ruler, the state, and the rulers\u00E2\u0080\u0099 subjects.17 1.2 Sage-Kings During the Warring States and early imperial eras, tales about the sage-kings were central in many mythological \u00E2\u0080\u009Caccounts of ancient history and the emergence of human 15 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 53. 16 Ibid., 15; 53. 17 Ibid., 53. 7 civilization,\u00E2\u0080\u009D which were some of the most salient ways through which the early Chinese were able to conceptualize their cosmological views and to express their understanding of their own positions within that framework. 18 Of the many myths about the sage-kings, some of the more important ones include the following: 1) Yu \u00E7\u00A6\u00B9, who was responsible for taming the great flood and for the construction of irrigation 19 ; 2) Yao \u00E5\u00A0\u00AF and Shun \u00E8\u0088\u009C, who were not only moral exemplars and virtuous rulers, but who also yielded the throne to those whom they deemed more worthy 20 ; 3) Shennong \u00E7\u00A5\u009E\u00E8\u00BE\u00B2, who was credited with the invention of agriculture and medicine 21 ; and also 4) Huangdi \u00E9\u00BB\u0083\u00E5\u00B8\u009D, the Yellow Emperor, who created a government and demarcated human society from the wild animals. 22 These purported achievements and the individuals\u00E2\u0080\u0099 characterization as semi-divine humans are what come to mind when the sage-kings narratives are discussed. Despite the centrality of these figures in the discourses of the time, they are difficult to clearly define and analyze\u00E2\u0080\u0094not only because of their elusive mythological origins, but also because of the many ways in which they were continuously being redefined in different texts and 18 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 167. 19 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 169; Mark Edward Lewis, Flood Myths of Early China (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2006), 16\u00E2\u0080\u009317. 20 Julia Ching, Mysticism and Kingship in China: The Heart of Chinese Wisdom (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1997), 59; Sarah Allan, The Heir and the Sage: Dynastic Legend in Early China (San Francisco, CA: Chinese Materials Center, 1981), 27\u00E2\u0080\u009328. 21 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 168; A. C. Graham, Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China (Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing, 1989), 66. 22 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 174; Michael J. Puett, \"Sage, Ministers, and Rebels,\" The Ambivalence of Creation: Debates Concerning Innovation and Artifice in Early China (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001), 98\u00E2\u0080\u009399. 8 contexts. These challenges aside, however, the concept of the sage-kings was employed liberally by most authors who composed during the Warring States period. 23 It is this prevalence among the texts that makes the concept a useful category of analysis to employ in an attempt to understand the political ideals that each of the texts represented, due to the central role that the sage-king concept plays within their intellectual frameworks. Furthermore, by examining how these narratives of the sage-kings were employed by the authors themselves, it will be possible to appropriately contextualize them within the greater context of Warring States intellectual history through comparisons with other contemporary texts. In essence, by basing their own political ideals in the supposed teachings of the sage-kings of old, or by offering their own interpretations of what those teachings entailed, the authors of these texts were able to find not only sanctions for their claims, but even political legitimacy, to the detriment of those who held different opinions. 24 23 Shinjiro Yoshinaga, \u00E2\u0080\u009CM\u00C5\u008Dshi ni okeru S\u00C4\u0093\u00C5\u008D to Seinin: sono Bokka shis\u00C5\u008D no juy\u00C5\u008D\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E5\u00AD\u009F\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E3\u0081\u00AB\u00E3\u0081\u008A\u00E3\u0081\u0091\u00E3\u0082\u008B\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E3\u0081\u00A8\u00E8\u0081\u0096 \u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E3\u0081\u009D\u00E3\u0081\u00AE\u00E5\u00A2\u00A8\u00E5\u00AE\u00B6\u00E6\u0080\u009D\u00E6\u0083\u00B3\u00E3\u0081\u00AE\u00E5\u008F\u0097\u00E5\u00AE\u00B9, Akita Daigaku ky\u00C5\u008Diku gakubu kenky\u00C5\u00AB kiy\u00C5\u008D\u00EF\u00BC\u009Ajinbun kagaku shakai kagaku \u00E7\u00A7\u008B\u00E7\u0094\u00B0 \u00E5\u00A4\u00A7\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6\u00E6\u0095\u0099\u00E8\u0082\u00B2\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6\u00E9\u0083\u00A8\u00E7\u00A0\u0094\u00E7\u00A9\u00B6\u00E7\u00B4\u0080\u00E8\u00A6\u0081 \u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E6\u0096\u0087\u00E7\u00A7\u0091\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6\u00E3\u0083\u00BB\u00E7\u00A4\u00BE\u00E4\u00BC\u009A\u00E7\u00A7\u0091\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6 48 (1995): 53; Deng Guoguang (Tang Kwok Kwong) \u00E9\u0084\u00A7\u00E5\u009C\u008B \u00E5\u0085\u0089, Shengwang zhi Dao: Xian Qin zhuzi de jingshi zhihui \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E2\u0080\u0094\u00E5\u0085\u0088\u00E7\u00A7\u00A6\u00E8\u00AB\u00B8\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E7\u009A\u0084\u00E7\u00B6\u0093\u00E4\u00B8\u0096\u00E6\u0099\u00BA\u00E6\u0085\u00A7 (Beijing, China: Zhonghua shuju chubanshe, 2010), 158. According to Yoshinaga, \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B as a set phrase does not occur in the received versions of the following texts: Book of Odes \u00E8\u00A9\u00A9\u00E7\u00B6\u0093, Book of Documents \u00E6\u009B\u00B8\u00E7\u00B6\u0093, the Analects \u00E8\u00AB\u0096\u00E8\u00AA\u009E, the Spring and Autumn Annals \u00E6\u0098\u00A5\u00E7\u00A7\u008B, the Sunzi \u00E5\u00AD\u00AB\u00E5\u00AD\u0090, the Daodejing \u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E5\u00BE\u00B7\u00E7\u00B6\u0093, and the Zhuangzi \u00E8\u008E\u008A\u00E5\u00AD\u0090; it does, however, occur in the following texts: the Mozi \u00E5\u00A2\u00A8\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 (121 instances), the Guoy\u00C3\u00BC \u00E5\u009C\u008B \u00E8\u00AA\u009E (eight instances), Zuo Commentaries \u00E5\u00B7\u00A6\u00E5\u0082\u00B3 (three instances), the Mencius \u00E5\u00AD\u009F\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 (one instance), the Guanzi \u00E7\u00AE\u00A1\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 (forty-five instances), Book of Lord Shang \u00E5\u0095\u0086\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E6\u009B\u00B8(five instances), Stratagems of the Warring States \u00E6\u0088\u00B0\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E7\u00AD\u0096(two instances), the Xunzi \u00E8\u008D\u0080\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 (thirty-seven instances), the Classic of Ritual \u00E7\u00A6\u00AE\u00E8\u00A8\u0098 (ten instances), the Hanfeizi \u00E9\u009F\u0093\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 (nine instances), and the Annals of L\u00C3\u00BC \u00E5\u0091\u0082\u00E6\u00B0\u008F\u00E6\u0098\u00A5\u00E7\u00A7\u008B (twenty instances). Deng cites Yoshinaga and further points out that \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king\u00E2\u0080\u009D can be observed from the Yanzi Chunqiu \u00E6\u0099\u008F \u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E6\u0098\u00A5\u00E7\u00A7\u008B as well. 24 Mark Edward Lewis, Writing and Authority in Early China (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1999), 123. 9 As much contemporary scholarship has pointed out, the sage-kings were an integral aspect of Warring States thought, especially serving as the locus for much of the discourse when it came to idealized rulership. One suggestion posited by Julia Ching is that these sage-kings were the humanized forms of deities from earlier shamanistic traditions. 25 Another view posited by Mark Csikszentmihalyi and Michael Nylan is that they were largely reconstructed figures in later periods, characterized by the features of multiple primitive deities, and that they were generated for specific intellectual or religious debates about cosmology, human nature, and political legitimacy, just to name a few uses. 26 Some contemporary scholars such as Pines and Sarah Allan have depicted the concept of the sage-kings in the development of Chinese political thought over the last two millennia as its integral central feature, which essentializes the entire political experience. 27 Others have merely recognized the concept as an idealized embodiment of political order and legitimacy, divorced from the real exercises of power and the exertion of political control of the imperial centre over the periphery. 28 One of the most fundamental features in Warring States thought was the employment of sage-kings as moral exemplars by authors who urged rulers to aspire to realizing the vision of unifying All-under-Heaven by emulating their sagacious governance. In this vein, Lewis conveys a very succinct image of the sage-kings, who were described thusly: \u00E2\u0080\u00A6superhuman beings whose wisdom allowed them to recognize the celestial patterns hidden in nature and bring mankind into accord with them. To the sages were attributed all the tools and procedures that formed the Chinese civilization, and the invention of tools...became a hallmark of the sage-kings denied to lesser beings. [Furthermore, they] introduced all those values, institutions, and regular 25 Ching, Mysticism and Kingship, 5. 26 Csikszentmihalyi and Nylan, \u00E2\u0080\u009CConstructing Lineages,\u00E2\u0080\u009D 99. 27 Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire,109; Allan, Heir and the Sage, 3-6. 28 Lewis, Writing and Authority, 123. 10 practices that made possible a truly human existence as this was understood. 29 In addition, the historicity of the sage-king figures themselves is a question that, although interesting, has already been discussed by prominent Chinese scholars in the larger context of the doubting the antiquities \u00E7\u0096\u0091\u00E5\u008F\u00A4 movement during the early part of the twentieth century, led by Gu Jiegang \u00E9\u00A1\u00A7\u00E9\u00A0\u00A1\u00E5\u0089\u009B and his associates with the journal Gushibian \u00E5\u008F\u00A4\u00E5\u008F\u00B2\u00E8\u00BE\u00A8 (Discriminations on Ancient History). One of the major contributions of Gu to the study of early Chinese mythologies is the claim that it seems that in the earliest texts, only the sage Yu is utilized; however, in later texts like the Analects and the Mozi \u00E5\u00A2\u00A8\u00E5\u00AD\u0090, sages such as Yao and Shun were added to the pantheon of sage-kings who were deemed even more ancient than Yu. This process continued throughout the Warring States and early imperial eras, so that figures such as Huangdi, Shennong, the Three Sovereigns \u00E4\u00B8\u0089\u00E7\u009A\u0087, and eventually even Pangu \u00E7\u009B\u00A4\u00E5\u008F\u00A4 were introduced.30 In other words, as Puett very succinctly points out, \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe later the text, the older were the sages portrayed therein.\u00E2\u0080\u009D31 This led to the well-known conclusion that many of the mythologies surrounding the revered sage-kings prevalent in early Chinese texts were presumably Warring States and early Han inventions, fabricated for particular narratives or to fulfill specific rhetorical or philosophical purposes of the authors of these texts. The above scholars have all defined the sage-kings slightly differently, and they emphasize different features that collectively create the heterogeneous nature of this 29 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 167. 30 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 93 31 Ibid., 94. 11 concept. Excepting notable scholars like Puett and Lewis, there have been very few who have attempted to reexamine this often overlooked concept systematically. It is with this in mind that I believe it is appropriate to focus my research on summarizing and assessing the current state of academic research on the sage-kings, with the goal of questioning our current understanding of this important feature in the development of early Chinese political philosophy. 1.3 Statement of Research Questions Many sinologists have explicated, to varying degrees, the concept of the sage- king in their research, and there is a general recognition that this concept is an important part of our understanding of the historical development of early Chinese political thought. Based on this consensus, my research seeks to survey and analyze how these scholars have conceptualized the use of the sage-kings by the authors of the Warring States texts, and especially how those authors used the idea to promote their own specific political ideals. Furthermore, I will argue that the tales of the sage-kings were not mere mythological or historical accounts. Rather, they form narratives that encapsulate the intention of the authors of these texts, and the ways in which the texts were defined, redefined, and utilized were constantly changing. Focusing on how the sage-kings were used allows for a better understanding of the historical contexts that brought these authors to espouse the ideas that they did and to compose these treatises in the ways that they did. With this in mind, my thesis will first survey and examine how contemporary scholarship has attempted to reconstruct and understand the development of Warring 12 States political philosophy through the use of the sage-kings. To this end, I will examine how scholars have addressed the following topics: 1) the crucial tension between mythology and history in the formulation of the sage-kings concept, 2) the putative role that sage-kings played as the primogenitors of civilization, and 3) the divergent ways that Warring States texts have used and presented the sage-king figures and how best to systematically extricate them from the texts in order to gain a comprehensive understanding of the constantly changing political realities of the time. Having done that, I will proceed to examine two examples of the sage-kings being portrayed in the Warring States texts, for their significance with respect to political narratives and their demonstration of the evolution of these narratives. I will give a preliminary analysis of how each of these narratives addressed particular political needs at their inception and whether the texts\u00E2\u0080\u0099 interpretation by Warring States authors changed over time or largely stayed the same. Specifically, I will be looking at the following: 1) the myths pertaining to the taming of the great flood by Yu \u00E7\u00A6\u00B9, which can be interpreted as a way to rationalize both the creation of human civilization from disorder and chaos as well as the formation of boundaries that distinguish what is essentially human from the non-human; and 2) the example of Yao \u00E5\u00A0\u00AF and Shun \u00E8\u0088\u009C, which illustrates the important question of legitimate succession and the transfer of political power from one ruler to the next. 13 1.4 Methodological Matters The methodological practices employed in this thesis are primarily inspired by Professor Michael Puett, whose very careful analysis of existing secondary scholarship and emphasis on properly contextualizing Warring States texts and the various philosophical debates within their original historical contexts in both To become a God: Cosmology, Sacrifice, and Self-Divinization in Early China as well as The Ambivalence of Creation: Debates Concerning Innovation and Artifice in Early China, have been truly illuminating for my own research. I find his methodological approach not only effective in contextualizing my own research within the existing historiography of the concept of the ideal ruler in Warring States thought, but it also will allow me to take a more global approach when I attempt to analyze primary source documents using the theories that contemporary scholarship has advanced. As Puett has argued, \u00E2\u0080\u009C[t]he method of analysis should be to isolate the tensions that generated the debates, analyze the history of those debates, and, when comparing, to do so only when one has isolated in other cultures similar problems.\u00E2\u0080\u009D32 That is to say, rather than focusing on merely drawing comparisons, and in turn conclusions, from particularities of individual ideas within larger debates across cultures, it would be more appropriate first to identify and then to understand the larger contexts in which those debates were taking place. It is with this in mind, then, that I attempt to survey the current field of research with the focus on secondary scholarship, in order to, if not reconstruct, at least to gain a relatively macroscopic picture of what scholars have been conveying in the past two 32 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 20. 14 decades. I will spend the first half of this thesis extrapolating various arguments and observations with regards to the issue of sage-kings that have been made by leading scholars published in English as well as by a limited number of East Asian scholars who have published their research in Chinese and Japanese. This is to serve as a basic foundation upon which to adequately construct manageable categories of analysis of the concept of the sage-king. By no means will this thesis be able to conduct a truly exhaustive analysis of all the sage-kings in Classical Chinese texts, nor will it be able to look at all the different instances in which the authors of these texts postulate concepts of ideal rulership. Much of this is something that I plan to pursue in my future research, especially with the intention of using the information derived from newly discovered archaeological manuscripts. 15 2. Sage-King Narratives: A Contemporary Tale During the Warring States and early imperial periods, tales about the sage-kings were central in many mythological \u00E2\u0080\u009Caccounts of ancient history and the emergence of human civilization,\u00E2\u0080\u009D which were some of the most salient ways through which the early Chinese were able to conceptualize their cosmological views and to express their understanding of their own positions within that framework. 33 It is posited by many scholars that much of the Warring States discourse regarding the sage-kings was largely mythological in nature and the different sources of these myths could be used to explain the divergent interpretations by these texts. That being said, the sage-kings were interpreted differently not just by the authors of the various Warring States texts. Scholars today, too, offer many different opinions with regards to the origins of these narratives, how they came to be integrated within the collective public consciousness of the Warring States authors, and also what their significance was and what kinds of insights could be extrapolated to shed light on the political and intellectual realities of the time. 2.1 Myth, Shamanism, and Sage-King Narratives In any discussion of the sage-king narratives and the role that they play within the intellectual consciousness during the Warring States period, it is absolutely essential to examine their relationship to the historical conceptions of the past on the part of the authors and also, inevitably, to examine the dynamic between history and mythology. The narratives of the sage-kings were constructed by authors who lived during a time 33 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 16. 16 when the development of states \u00E2\u0080\u009Cdevoted to centralization, strong legal structures, and a large-scale mobilization of peasants for the sake of war\u00E2\u0080\u009D was taking place.34 These kinds of fundamental changes in state organization and state-society relations not only defined the kinds of philosophical debates that were occurring, but they also reveal the fact that not everyone wholeheartedly agreed with the kinds of developments that were being undertaken by these warring states. It is this kind of historical context in which intellectuals at the time attempted to comprehend, legitimize, or altogether undermine these political developments through the use of the sage-king concept within the historical and mythological discourses about the origins of the state and kingship in the distant past. One more point of contention, then, is whether the authors of these texts themselves recognized the fact that these sage-king figures were merely mythological, or whether they in fact interpreted them as genuine historical rulers who existed in the past. Furthermore, it will inevitably affect the ways in which current scholars interpret these texts and, in turn, formulate their own understandings with regards to the sage-kings. It is perplexing to me how it is demonstratively evident that sage-king figures were mythological figures, yet on the other hand, they held considerable influence over the historical development of political discourses during the Warring States period. For the purpose of my research, I have opted to follow Lewis\u00E2\u0080\u0099s definition of myths, which he posits are \u00E2\u0080\u009Cstories which \u00E2\u0080\u0098express dramatically the ideology under which a society lives,\u00E2\u0080\u0099 that reflect the rules and traditional practices without which everything within a society would disintegrate.\u00E2\u0080\u009D35 Despite the efforts of many scholars during the twentieth century 34 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 92. 35 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 167. 17 to organize and pinpoint the origins of these myths, just as Derek Bodde reveals, these materials are \u00E2\u0080\u009Cusually so fragmentary and episodic that even the reconstruction from them of individual myths\u00E2\u0080\u0094let alone an integrated system of myths\u00E2\u0080\u0094is exceedingly difficult.\u00E2\u0080\u009D36 With regards to this question of the inherent conceptual mystique and authority of the sage-kings, Ching attributes them to earlier, more primitive concepts of kingship that arose out of the shamanic tradition. 37 As she points out, \u00E2\u0080\u009CThe sage-king paradigm arose out of the experience of ancient shamanic rulers, even if, in some ways the gradual eclipse of ecstasy was accompanied by the growth of ethics and exegesis.\u00E2\u0080\u009D38 That is to say, as the mystique and claims to transcendental authority of shamans either decreased or were transformed into that based on a more robust systematic framework of moral and political philosophies, the sage-king developed both as a political concept and as a philosophical ideal. It is interesting to note that the view that early Chinese notions of kingship were indeed shamanic is not without its own controversies, and there exists disagreement within current scholarship. For instance, despite reservations, Lothar von Falkenhausen agrees with Ching in principle, and both accept K. C. Chang\u00E2\u0080\u0099s proposed explanatory framework, which suggests a certain degree of correlation between shamanistic practices and the development of concepts of kingship in early China. 39 Chang points to the 36 As cited in Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 92\u00E2\u0080\u009393. 37 Ching, Mysticism and Kingship, 5. 38 Ibid., xvii. 39 K. C. Chang, Art, Myth, and Ritual: The Path to Political Authority in Ancient China (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983), 44\u00E2\u0080\u009355; Lothar von Falkenhausen, Chinese Society in the Age of Confucius (1000\u00E2\u0080\u0093250 BC): The Archaeological Evidence (Los Angeles, CA: Cotsen Institute of Archaeology, UCLA, 18 importance of divination and to the use of ritual bronze sacrificial vessels with animal designs in the Shang and Zhou polities, as means both to commune and to interact with the spiritual world. 40 In particular, von Falkenhausen argues that while a concise definition of \u00E2\u0080\u009Cshamanism\u00E2\u0080\u009D is still subject to debate, the fact is that it is \u00E2\u0080\u009Cnot a particular kind of religion, but a religious technique that can be\u00E2\u0080\u00A6employed in the service of the most diverse theologies.\u00E2\u0080\u009D41 In other words, rather than interpreting \u00E2\u0080\u009Cshamanic\u00E2\u0080\u009D as a term that reveals the complexities of the theology in early Chinese religion, one can use it to describe some of the religious practices that have been observed. Nonetheless, others like David Keightly reject this direct connection between shamanism and political institutions in the Shang, arguing that instead, the hierarchical and \u00E2\u0080\u009Cbureaucratic\u00E2\u0080\u009D religious beliefs and practices of the Shang could be \u00E2\u0080\u009Ccharacterized as nonreligious, nonmysterious, and\u00E2\u0080\u0094because so explicitly goal directed\u00E2\u0080\u0094rational, in [their] logic.\u00E2\u0080\u009D42 On the other hand, Puett questions both of these interpretations of the sacral, religious aspects of kingship in early Chinese thought, criticizing the prevailing assumption of an inherent harmony between the spiritual and human worlds and claiming that ritual practices were instituted \u00E2\u0080\u009Cto domesticate the spirits and thereby render them controllable.\u00E2\u0080\u009D43 Thus a rather more complicated picture of their relationship to the spiritual world and their correlation to political authority can be extrapolated from these different interpretations. Understanding this background is indispensable in treating the 2006), 47. 40 Chang, Art, Myth, and Ritual, 54; 80. 41 Von Falkenhausen, Chinese Society in the Age of Confucius, 47. 42 David N. Keightley, \"The Religious Commitment: Shang Theology and the Genesis of Chinese Political Culture,\" History of Religion, 17 (1978): 214. 43 Michael Puett, To Become a God: Cosmology, Sacrifice, and Self-Divinization in Early China (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Asia Center, 2002), 50\u00E2\u0080\u009354. 19 analysis of the concept of the sage-king, mostly because of the significant conceptual role that it plays in both the philosophical discourses and political rhetoric of the time. In spite of these conceptual connections with the shamanistic tradition, however, Ching claims that regarding the historicity of these sage-kings, it is more likely that the sage-kings were mythological, while there is a stronger possibility that the so-called Five Emperors might have indeed been real, owing to the fact that there is more textual information about them. 44 Claims like these are clearly problematic, not least because the mere abundance of textual materials on these figures not only does not prove those figures\u00E2\u0080\u0099 existence, but it merely demonstrates the fact that they were prominently invoked as literary figures in the texts that were compiled at the time. Ching recognizes this point as well and points out that sage-kings, as such, most likely never existed in reality and were instead mythical creations of later periods, used in order both to allude to the \u00E2\u0080\u009Cvague memory of shamanic rulers of the past\u00E2\u0080\u009D and also \u00E2\u0080\u009Cfor the sake of having real rulers emulate such mythical figures as Yao and Shun.\u00E2\u0080\u009D45 What is interesting about her observation here is that perhaps the reasons why the sage-kings were so prevalent as a concept in the intellectual discourse of the time was precisely that they were so malleable yet undoubtedly commanded a certain level of reverence among the ruling classes. What is unclear in her explications here, however, is why in particular the sage-kings were chosen and used by the philosophers of the time both to reinforce and legitimize their political ideals. Ching claims that even if these sage-kings were not actual historical figures and 44 Ibid., 56. 45 Ibid., xii. 20 were mythical fabrications, their significance in the overall development of Chinese political thought over the past two millennia was still substantial. For despite the \u00E2\u0080\u009Cmoral and historical ambiguity surrounding these early legends and historical accounts,\u00E2\u0080\u009D the significance lies in the fact that those champions of the sage-kings, namely the philosophers, \u00E2\u0080\u009Cpromoted the idea that the wise were fit to govern, if not as rulers, then at least as councillors.\u00E2\u0080\u009D46 Ching recognizes that what she calls the \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king paradigm\u00E2\u0080\u009D ultimately changed and transformed over time, and that regardless of its mythical origins stemming from notions of sacral kingship with all the rituals that came with that, this paradigm would continue to play a significant role within the early Chinese cosmological conceptual framework for centuries to come. Many scholars like Ching have posited that the myth of the sage-kings arose from the shamanistic traditions and practices in prehistoric times in early China. Nonetheless, it is also just as likely that the sage-kings largely came out of an earlier oral mythological tradition and came to be recorded during the Spring and Autumn as well as during the Warring States periods. It remains to be ascertained, with further archaeological and philological research, whether or not this was indeed the case. Just as Lewis points out, these prominent myths with \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe scattered references to the various sage-kings in surviving documents lack the tidy, systematic character\u00E2\u0080\u009D as many scholars who have undertaken myth reconstruction would discover. 47 These myths reflect, on the one hand, their disparate origins ranging from various shamanistic traditions across different regions to folklore that has been transmitted orally for generations before being recorded 46 Ching, Mysticism and Kingship, 60. 47 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 168. 21 in historical documents, and on the other hand, the various changes and transformations that could have taken place as they were recorded and posited by various authors for their own purposes. While it is difficult to delineate a clear process by which this took place, what contemporary scholars do recognize and can argue is that these myths and narratives, regardless of their origins, developed and changed over time and were constantly reacting to different influences. Having discussed the role that shamanistic historical developments played in the formation of the sage-king narratives, it would be appropriate to examine some of the many different ways that the Warring States authors chose to depict these mythological figures. 2.2 Sage-Kings and the Philosophical Masters From the shamanistic prehistoric past to the successive development of state structures by the Shang and Zhou dynasties, narratives about deities turned into tales about past cultural heroes in the form of sage-kings who, as Schwartz points out, \u00E2\u0080\u009Cmay be individuals but they are also superhumans who embody public truth.\u00E2\u0080\u009D48 The sage-kings, in turn, became virtuous moral paragons, creators of righteous governance, defenders of nature, inventors of laws and measures, or champions of the triumph of human civilization, depending on which texts are used in an attempt to systematically create concrete definitions and characteristics. Another indispensable aspect of the sage-king 48 Benjamin I. Schwartz, The World of Thought in Ancient China (Cambridge, MA and London, UK: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1985), 401. 22 figures is their role as technological innovators, cultural heroes, and ultimately their perceived status as the primogenitors of what would become \u00E2\u0080\u009CChinese\u00E2\u0080\u009D civilization. Clearly, there are times when the traits are complementary, for instance, it was possible for the sage-kings to champion human civilization and create government bureaucracies at the same time; however, contradictions were similarly likely. What, then, is the reason behind the fact that these authors all recognize and call upon a common set of figures, only to define and characterize them differently? In essence, the sage-kings became mouthpieces for these authors, who sought to advance their own philosophical ideals. Through the sage-kings\u00E2\u0080\u0099 perceived significance either in history or mythology, philosophical masters came to formulate ideas and compose treatises that eventually became the foundation of Chinese philosophy. This section will first look at how different texts depicted the sage-kings, how they constantly changed, and what different political ideals they represented within the broader context of the developing narratives about the warring states. Then it will address how scholars have attempted to mitigate the clear discrepancies in the portrayal of the sage-kings by the authors of these texts. For the purpose of this discussion, the significance of these sage-kings lies not in what they were presumed to have done, but in what they represented in the minds of the Warring States thinkers. 49 Similarly, while traces of the philosophical distinctiveness of each of the sage-kings were retained as time went on, they nevertheless began to share common attributes with one another. Narratives about these sage-kings \u00E2\u0080\u009Cgradually 49 Michael Puett, \u00E2\u0080\u009CSages, Ministers, and Rebels: Narratives from Early China Concerning the Initial Creation of the State,\u00E2\u0080\u009D Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 58 (1998): 427. 23 formed a coherent, meaningful body of myths that articulated the interests, concerns and dilemmas\u00E2\u0080\u009D of the ruling elite and \u00E2\u0080\u009Cconstituted a mythology of statecraft\u00E2\u0080\u009D that dealt with major themes of governance and political legitimacy. 50 Furthermore, as Lewis points out, the sage-kings as a collective entity, for instance in the myths of Yao and Shun, dealt with issues of political succession and heredity of power, while the legends of Huangdi dealt with matters of political violence and the triumph of humanistic order against chaotic, animalistic nature. The virtuous governance of these sage-kings was said to be unmatched, and thus the people under their rule lived in peace and prosperity. Indeed, this idea that humanity and human civilization has been in essence the work of sage-kings was a common theme among the many Warring States texts; how they differed, though, was in defining and portraying the ideals that these sage-kings would have wanted human society to aspire to. The texts would often start off by addressing various issues and problems that they perceived to be the cause of the malaise that plagues human society, be they either harsh political realities or the negative effects of the policies of others. Then they would explicate their own ideals, usually employing the sage-king figures as a way to bolster the legitimacy of their claims and to justify their policies as the most efficacious. In doing so, just as these authors were able to construct what they perceived to be the ideal methods to establish political order, reorganize society, and regulate the relationship between these two through the use of these myths, in turn, the myths themselves were recreated and transmitted for use by future generations. 50 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 169. 24 As can be seen in texts like the Analects, the Mencius \u00E5\u00AD\u009F\u00E5\u00AD\u0090, and the Mozi, these mythical figures represented a \u00E2\u0080\u009CGolden Age of the past when the people enjoyed peace and prosperity under the government of ideal rulers assisted by wise ministers.\u00E2\u0080\u009D51 While the Mozi is the only text among these three that uses the specific phrase \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king\u00E2\u0080\u009D systematically throughout, both the Analects and the Mencius would readily invoke the individual figures of sage-kings themselves to illustrate their own particular ideals. 52 To illustrate this, the sage-kings in the Analects were the ones who created music and ritual in order to regulate the relationships between humanity and the world. Though as Roger Ames questions: \u00E2\u0080\u009CYao and Shun, the sage rulers of high antiquity, accorded with the Way [\u00E9\u0081\u0093] in their governments, as did the early [Zhou] rulers, and yet Confucius looks to the latter as his primary exemplars\u00E2\u0080\u00A6Why then does Confucius favor the Chou rulers over Yao and Shun?\u00E2\u0080\u009D53 In fact, one of the ways in which the figure of Confucius of the Analects differs from other later texts like Mencius or Xunzi \u00E8\u008D\u0080\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 is his trust in the Zhou cultural institutions, ones that he believes have been established in accordance with the Way. Thus, perhaps in the mind of Confucius, since the times of Yao and Shun are long past and all that he does know for certain are the cultural inheritance and institutionalized rituals of the Zhou, those are the ones that he extols and attributes to the sage-kings. Similarly, following the teaching of Confucius, moral education will give the ability to any person, but especially to someone in the ruling elite, to transform his moral self and to transcend the circumstances that he was born into and become a gentleman. 51 Puett, To Become a God, 38. 52 Yoshinaga, \u00E2\u0080\u009CM\u00C5\u008Dshi ni okeru\u00E2\u0080\u009D, 53; Deng, Shengwang zhi Dao, 157. 53 Roger T. Ames, The Art of Rulership: A Study of Ancient Chinese Political Thought (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1994), 3. 25 Despite his \u00E2\u0080\u009Ctrust\u00E2\u0080\u00A6and love [of] the ancient ways\u00E2\u0080\u009D as well as his insistence that he \u00E2\u0080\u009Ctransmits rather than innovate[s],\u00E2\u0080\u009D in many ways, Confucius was truly a revolutionary figure by proposing that it was through moral cultivation and education that one could attain the virtuous legitimacy to rule. 54 Thus the political vision of the Analects was not merely returning the chaotic world under the rule of a sage-king, as this was also the aim of the other texts, but the vision was to do so within a very specific framework based on ritual propriety and filial piety, with a great emphasis on educating virtuous human beings. There even exist diverging views within two texts that both claim the legacy of being heirs to the ideals of Confucius, the Mencius and the Xunzi. The first of these was one of the most prominent texts in traditional Chinese political thought, especially after the dominance of neo-Confucianism and of highly influential figures such as Zhu Xi \u00E6\u009C\u00B1 \u00E7\u0086\u00B9 (1130 - 1200 CE), who were instrumental in its revitalization. According to the Mencius, and akin to a similar idea exhibited in the Analects, the sage-kings were the first ones who were concerned about the primordial disorder, where everything was presumed to be in chaos. It was the sage-kings who created and \u00E2\u0080\u009Ctaught the people the basic aspects of culture and morality\u00E2\u0080\u009D that were already innate in them; the sage-kings were merely teachers and organizers, not creators. 55 The significance of this was that while Confucius never quite made it explicit what precise role the sages-kings played during the formative years of humanity, the Mencius was unequivocal in positing that they were merely awakening all that was already innate in all human beings in order for them to realize 54 Analects, 7.1, trans. Slingerland, 64. 55 Puett, Ambivalence, 109. 26 \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe true hierarchy of nature.\u00E2\u0080\u009D56 In other words, the Mencius continued the same theme as the Analects in insisting that bringing about moral education was precisely the sage-king\u00E2\u0080\u0099s political role. Furthermore, it argues that even \u00E2\u0080\u009Cif they are well fed and have warm clothing and are comfortably lodged and are not taught, then they are close to beasts.\u00E2\u0080\u009D57 That is to say, mere technological advances and external developments of civilization are not sufficient to ensure that humans are truly distinguished from animals without also self-cultivation and the development of their internal inclinations for humaneness, or ren \u00E4\u00BB\u0081. In contrast, the Xunzi would emphasize quite the opposite and would insist on the need to cultivate the principles of ritual and righteousness in the people to save them from their natures. 58 In other words, the sage-kings in the Xunzi relied heavily on what Puett calls \u00E2\u0080\u009CHeaven- given faculties\u00E2\u0080\u009D to distinguish what is proper and what is not, in order to train and educate the people in such a way, leaving very little potential for the humans\u00E2\u0080\u0099 own natural tendencies to deviate from that order. 59 Thus the important role of the sage-kings in the Xunzi is to create institutions and social structures that are inherently external to humans, but necessary for human society. Even though the Mencius and Xunzi both invoke sage-king figures in their political ideals, and both emphasize the importance of moral education in their respective intellectual frameworks, they differ in their interpretations of what the sage-kings were thought to have done to bring about order in the world. 56 Ibid. 57 Schwartz, World of Thought, 269 58 Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire, 37; Geoffrey MacCormack, \u00E2\u0080\u009CMythology and the Origin of Law in Early Chinese Thought,\u00E2\u0080\u009D Journal of Asian Legal History 1 (2001), 5. 59 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 68. 27 Opposed to Confucius\u00E2\u0080\u0099s ideals, however, were ideas presented in texts such as the Mozi, in which the sage-kings were the ones who established laws, weights, measures, and proper names for different things in order to distinguish humans from beasts. 60 In particular, the Mozi argued that in primitive times, humans \u00E2\u0080\u009Cused the terms of moral judgment in whatever manner [they] chose;\u00E2\u0080\u009D thus the sage-kings regulated the use of language, especially with regards to moral judgments, to make social organization possible. 61 It is interesting to note that many of these issues were also ones that the Xunzi addresses, and that the later developments of these ideals about the sage-kings were either influenced by, or were composed as a response to the critiques of the Mozi. Similarly, in these texts, rather than the Confucian commitment to ritual propriety, what was given as the primary contribution of the sage-kings was the institution of law and punishment. As Puett discusses in his work, the Mozi argued that the reason for All-under-Heaven having fallen into a state of chaos was not that the sage-kings wrongly instituted the system of names and of law and punishments. Rather, it was because those very institutions were being wrongly utilized by wicked rulers to further their selfish needs. 62 The Mozi argued, particularly against the Confucian emphasis on placing filial piety and one\u00E2\u0080\u0099s family at the core of one\u00E2\u0080\u0099s social interactions, that impartiality is the key to right the many wrongs that their contemporary rulers, and also the Confucians, had inflicted upon the world. To this end, the necessity for the sage-kings to practice impartiality was revealed in the Mozi thus: \u00E2\u0080\u009CHeaven is all-inclusive and impartial in its activities, abundant and impartial in its blessings, lasting and unfailing in its guidance. Hence the Sage Kings modeled 60 Pines, Envisioning Enternal Empire, 28; MacCormack, \u00E2\u0080\u009CMythology and the Origin of Law\u00E2\u0080\u009D, 4; Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 170. 61 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 170. 62 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 106. 28 themselves upon it.\u00E2\u0080\u009D63 As a matter of fact, the Mozi abundantly uses the exact phrase, \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king,\u00E2\u0080\u009D as it appears in this text over a hundred times, more so than in any of the other Warring States texts. 64 However, the author of the Mozi also criticizes the tyrants, and it could be argued that in reality, all of the many explications of the \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king\u00E2\u0080\u009D were actually targeted at those very tyrants. Deng argues that it could be extrapolated from this that \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe ancient sage-kings\u00E2\u0080\u009D were not in reality the historical virtuous kings and illuminated rulers, but were instead used as antitheses to what the author considered to be the reality of his time; the sage-kings were in fact the ideal rulers in the minds of the author. 65 In contrast, the sage-king figure in the Daodejing \u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E5\u00BE\u00B7\u00E7\u00B6\u0093 would \u00E2\u0080\u009Cabide in the business of non-action\u00E2\u0080\u009D in order to \u00E2\u0080\u009Cempty the people\u00E2\u0080\u0099s heart [-minds] and fill their bellies\u00E2\u0080\u009D to return the people to the state of nature.66 That is to say, even being in a position of great political power, the sage-king would, in effect, carry out no actions and would attempt to ensure that there would be nothing else to disturb this \u00E2\u0080\u009Cnatural\u00E2\u0080\u009D progression of things. This idea is notable, as it represented one of the most prominent trends of primitivist thought, which regarded all artificial creations such as rituals, music, government, laws, and so forth, as being harmful to human nature. In this particular perspective, the sage-kings were the ones who engaged in no active governing, as 63 Mozi Chapter 4, Kung-chuan Hsiao, A History of Chinese Political Thought: Volume 1: From the Beginnings to the Sixth Century A.D., trans. F. W. Mote (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 243. 64 Yoshinaga, \u00E2\u0080\u009CM\u00C5\u008Dshi ni okeru\u00E2\u0080\u009D, 53. 65 Deng, Shengwang zhi Dao, 172. Traditionally the Daodejing is said to be composed by a person named Laozi, which is the reason that sometimes this text is also called the Laozi. Like most of the other Warring States texts, the actual author or compiler of the Daodejing itself remains unknown. 66 Philip J. Ivanhoe, trans. The Daodejing of Laozi (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 2002), 2; Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire, 37; MacCormack, \u00E2\u0080\u009CMythology and the Origin of Law\u00E2\u0080\u009D,5. 29 humans were not separated from the animals, and the authors of the Daodejing attributed all the chaos and warfare that plagued the Warring States period to these artificial creations by lesser rulers. As a result of their particular vision of ideal rulership, however, they denied the title of \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage\u00E2\u0080\u009D to figures like Yao and Shun and reserved that title for the ruler that would eventually return the world into its natural primal state, without the evils of human artificiality. 2.3 Late Warring States Critiques of Sage-Kings As the development of the Warring States period continued and the use of sage- king narratives started to evoke responses from different philosophers, not everyone was convinced that emulating and following the way of the sage-kings was truly what was best for restoring order to All-under-Heaven. A primary critic of the sage-kings was the text Zhuangzi \u00E8\u008E\u008A\u00E5\u00AD\u0090, which was a \u00E2\u0080\u009Cfull length book for the individual who wants to live his own life free of the burdens of office\u00E2\u0080\u00A6[and was] in effect an anthology of writings with philosophies justifying withdrawal to private life.\u00E2\u0080\u009D67 It should be noted that the Zhuangzi has been recognized to be a heterogeneous text, and some of its contents are only related to the main themes of the book, as depicted in the Inner Chapters, only marginally. 68 The Inner Chapters depict the \u00E2\u0080\u009C\u00E2\u0080\u0098free and wandering\u00E2\u0080\u0099\u00E2\u0080\u009D sages grounded in the Dao, as well as the \u00E2\u0080\u009Crelativity of all conceptual categorization and equanimity towards 67 Graham, Disputers of the Tao, 172. 68 H. D. Roth, \u00E2\u0080\u009CChuang tzu,\u00E2\u0080\u009D in Early Chinese Texts: A Bibliographical Guide, ed. Michael Loewe (Berkeley, CA: The Society for the Study of Early China and the Institute of East Asian Studies, 1993), 56. 30 life and death.\u00E2\u0080\u009D69 Within the Inner Chapters, it is possible to find sages who actively engage in the practices of society, even some of the Confucian practices that the more primitivist chapters criticize. It is from within these chapters that it is possible to extract a different kind of critique against the sage-kings in the late Warring States intellectual landscape. Interestingly, the Zhuangzi does not use the term \u00E2\u0080\u009Csage-king\u00E2\u0080\u009D at all, its critiques against the sages and its utter disdain for the ways of the sage-kings is unequivocal, as can be observed from passages like the following: Then along came the sage. Limping and staggering after Humanity, straining on tiptoes after Responsibility, they filled everyone in the world with self-doubt. Lasciviously slobbering over music, fastidiously obsessing over ritual, they got everyone in the world to take sides. \u00E2\u0080\u00A6unless you drop the [Way] and its Virtuosity, how can you take up [Benevolence] and [Righteousness]? Unless our inborn nature and our uncontrived condition are dismembered, what use will there be for ritual and music? \u00E2\u0080\u00A6The destruction of the [Way] and its Virtuosity to make [Benevolence] and [Righteousness] is the fault of the sages. 70 In essence, these kinds of critiques, especially against the kinds of virtues that are held dear by the Confucians, are very standard for the more Zhuangzi. It questions whether or not the values that these sages are deemed to represent, such as benevolence and righteousness, are not merely hypocritical values that actually distract from the overall soteriology of becoming attuned with the Way, which would have been fully compatible with human nature had it not been for the superfluous artificialities like ritual and music. A similar sentiment is reflected in the \u00E2\u0080\u009CRobber Zhi\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E7\u009B\u009C\u00E8\u00B7\u0096 chapter, in which the author not only lambastes the purported moral character of the sage-kings but also mocks 69 Ibid. 70 Zhuangzi : The Essential Writings with Selections from Traditional Commentaries, Chapter 9, trans. Brook Ziporyn (Indianopolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company Inc., 2009), 61\u00E2\u0080\u009362. \u00E5\u008F\u008A\u00E8\u0087\u00B3\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u00B9\u00A9\u00E8\u00BA\u00A0\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BB\u0081\u00EF\u00BC\u008C \u00E8\u00B8\u00B6\u00E8\u00B7\u0082\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E7\u00BE\u00A9\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E5\u00A7\u008B\u00E7\u0096\u0091\u00E7\u009F\u00A3\u00EF\u00BC\u009B\u00E6\u00BE\u00B6\u00E6\u00BC\u00AB\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E6\u00A8\u0082\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u0091\u0098\u00E5\u0083\u00BB\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E7\u00A6\u00AE\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E5\u00A7\u008B\u00E5\u0088\u0086\u00E7\u009F\u00A3\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E5\u00BE\u00B7\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E5\u00BB\u00A2\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u00AE\u0089\u00E5\u008F\u0096\u00E4\u00BB\u0081\u00E7\u00BE\u00A9\u00EF\u00BC\u0081\u00E6\u0080\u00A7\u00E6\u0083\u0085\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E9\u009B\u00A2\u00EF\u00BC\u008C \u00E5\u00AE\u0089\u00E7\u0094\u00A8\u00E7\u00A6\u00AE\u00E6\u00A8\u0082\u00EF\u00BC\u0081\u00E6\u00AF\u0080\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E5\u00BE\u00B7\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BB\u0081\u00E7\u00BE\u00A9\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E9\u0081\u008E\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082 31 their actions: Huang Di was unable to sustain virtue: he fought Chi You at the Zhuolu fields, and the blood flowed for a hundred miles. When Yao and Shun appeared, they established multitudes of ministers. [Then] Tang banished his sovereign, and King Wu killed [his ruler], Zhou [\u00E7\u00B4\u0082]. From then on, the strong oppressed the weak; the many abused the few. Since the time of Tang and Wu, everybody follows these calamitous people. 71 First of all, it should be pointed out that the sage-king figure of Huang Di was probably a Warring States creation, as he does not appear in any of the surviving documentary sources that predate this period. Nonetheless, the Zhuangzi would definitely take issue with Huang Di, as he was perceived to be a militaristic figure, especially associated with the \u00E2\u0080\u009Corganized used of violence by the state, either in terms of punishing the wicked, subjugating rebels, or dealing with barbarians, as sanctioned by the divine Heaven.\u00E2\u0080\u009D72 The comment here about Huang Di not being able to \u00E2\u0080\u009Csustain virtue\u00E2\u0080\u009D is a clear critique of the states\u00E2\u0080\u0099 increasingly rampant use of military means to achieve their political goals. Similarly, the creation of a bureaucracy in the form of \u00E2\u0080\u009Cmultitudes of ministers\u00E2\u0080\u009D by Yao and Shun is equally problematic for a philosopher whose ideal is to retreat from worldly engagements. Perhaps the most damning of all indictments in this passage are the final two, lobbed against rulers who are traditionally considered sagacious but who are instead criticized as being usurpers. With the main message being that not only are the ways of the sage-kings abhorrent, making matters worse is the fact that the contemporaries of the author \u00E2\u0080\u009C[follow] these calamitous people.\u00E2\u0080\u009D As a whole, it is clear that the development of the sage-kings narrative has indeed taken a change during the Warring States period, for 71 Zhuangzi \u00E2\u0080\u009CDao Zhi\u00E2\u0080\u009D Chapter, trans. Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire, 79-80. \u00E7\u0084\u00B6\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E9\u00BB\u0083\u00E5\u00B8\u009D\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E8\u0083\u00BD\u00E8\u0087\u00B4\u00E5\u00BE\u00B7\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0088\u0087 \u00E8\u009A\u00A9\u00E5\u00B0\u00A4\u00E6\u0088\u00B0\u00E6\u0096\u00BC\u00E6\u00B6\u00BF\u00E9\u00B9\u00BF\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E9\u0087\u008E\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B5\u0081\u00E8\u00A1\u0080\u00E7\u0099\u00BE\u00E9\u0087\u008C\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00E4\u00BD\u009C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E7\u00AB\u008B\u00E7\u00BE\u00A4\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B9\u00AF\u00E6\u0094\u00BE\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E4\u00B8\u00BB\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E6\u00AE\u00BA\u00E7\u00B4\u0082\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E8\u0087\u00AA\u00E6\u0098\u00AF\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E5\u00BE\u008C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E5\u00BC\u00B7\u00E9\u0099\u00B5\u00E5\u00BC\u00B1\u00EF\u00BC\u008C \u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u009C\u00BE\u00E6\u009A\u00B4\u00E5\u00AF\u00A1\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u00B9\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E4\u00BE\u0086\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E7\u009A\u0086\u00E4\u00BA\u0082\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E5\u00BE\u0092\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082 72 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 111. 32 not only were the sage-kings not respected by the Zhuangzi, they ultimately become targets for ridicule and become a means that the opponents of those who subscribe to these narratives can use to relentlessly attack them. Another late Warring States text shares with the Zhuangzi a similar sense of disdain for the sage-kings. The Hanfeizi \u00E9\u009F\u0093\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 is traditionally categorized as one of the fundamental so-called Legalist texts, along with others attributed to Shang Yang \u00E5\u0095\u0086\u00E9\u009E\u0085, Shen Dao \u00E6\u0085\u008E\u00E5\u0088\u00B0, and Shen Buhai \u00E7\u0094\u00B3\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E5\u00AE\u00B3. Compiled around the middle of the third century BCE, it is generally considered to be one of the latest Warring States texts and thus not only has it been considered to be an \u00E2\u0080\u009Caggregation, systematization, and clarification\u00E2\u0080\u009D of pre-Qin Legalist doctrines, but it is also capable of addressing many of the different arguments posited by some of the other prevailing thinkers on how best to solve the challenges of the time. 73 I am mostly interested in the Hanfeizi, because it represents a very specific and particular historical context, that of the late Warring States period, on the eve of the Qin conquest in 221 BCE. Furthermore, it is presented as a primarily ruler-centric political philosophy of state organization. The combination of these two features allows it to be historically aware of where it can situate its own arguments against those of the other authors, and furthermore, makes very clear the kinds of serious concerns that are relevant to the rulers who actually have the means to carry out the kinds of political practices that it proposes. It is true that many of the other Warring States texts, too, offer various suggestions to rulers on how best to rule and exert their power by means of self- 73 Ames, Art of Rulership, 84. 33 cultivation or by implementing reforms in their governance. But none of them seem to be nearly as single-minded in the focus of enabling the ruler to amass absolute control and power over the state. Furthermore, while the utter disregard and even dismissal of moral virtues in the Hanfeizi has maligned this text in the eyes of many later scholars influenced by Confucian teachings, the fact remains that the underlying political philosophy, comparatively devoid of interest in the ruler as a person and being more interested in the ruler as a component and embodiment of the state, is what I find particularly interesting. For the Hanfeizi, the ideal ruler would emphasize the use of laws and standards through the two handles of government, rewards and punishments, in order to reward the worthy and to punish those who went against the proper order as determined by the ruler. Just as this succinct summary by Ames suggests, this kind of legalist \u00E2\u0080\u009Cpolitical philosophy might be described as \u00E2\u0080\u0098government of the ruler, by the ruler, and for the ruler.\u00E2\u0080\u0099\u00E2\u0080\u009D74 This sentiment and the Hanfeizi\u00E2\u0080\u0099s conception of the ideal ruler are also reflected in the \u00E2\u0080\u009CZhudao\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E4\u00B8\u00BB\u00E9\u0081\u0093 (Way of Rulership) chapter. This chapter begins by very briefly discussing the cosmological significance of the ruler and his relationship to the supposed \u00E2\u0080\u009CWay of the Ruler,\u00E2\u0080\u009D as prescribed by the Dao. Nonetheless, the author spends a majority of this chapter in explicating what he perceives as the proper power dynamics between the ruler and his ministers and subjects. While he does not go into detail with regards to the organization of actual administrative structures, he is unequivocal in presenting the different responsibilities for the rulers and the ministers, what they should do and how they should act in carrying out the governance of the state. He also outlines the various threats and dangers to the state, and by extension to the ruler\u00E2\u0080\u0099s authority, and how they 74 Ames, Art of Rulership, 50. 34 ought to be dealt with. Interestingly, while the ruler as conceptualized in the Hanfeizi is omnipotent and omniscient, he in fact does not carry out any of the governing in reality, relegating all of those tasks to his ministers. He merely creates and maintains law and standards while functioning as someone who measures and controls the ministers by means of the \u00E2\u0080\u009Ctwo handles of governance:\u00E2\u0080\u009D rewards and punishments. Overall, this chapter summarizes most of the major concepts and themes in the Hanfeizi quite effectively. Most importantly, it highlights the qualities that an ideal ruler ought to have and how this ideal ruler should act in the running of the state bureaucracy. One of the first observations that can be made with regards to the philosophy of the Hanfeizi is the references that the author makes to the Dao, which is vacuous, primordial, creative, transcendental, and limitless. Many scholars have readily recognized the correlation between the thought of the Daodejing and the ideas in Hanfeizi, beginning as early as Sima Qian \u00E5\u008F\u00B8\u00E9\u00A6\u00AC\u00E9\u0081\u00B7 of the Han dynasty in the Shiji \u00E5\u008F\u00B2\u00E7\u00B4\u0080 (Record of the Grand Historian). 75 While it is not in the scope of this project to fully examine the implications of how earlier texts such as the Daodejing and others in the so called \u00E2\u0080\u009CHuang-Lao\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E9\u00BB\u0083\u00E8\u0080\u0081 tradition have influenced the development of the Hanfeizi, it is nonetheless interesting to note the borrowing of terminology among different ideological traditions. There are traits that, according to the Hanfeizi, are common to both the Dao and to concepts of fa \u00E6\u00B3\u0095, interpreted most commonly as law. 76 Just as the Dao is all-encompassing and the origin of all beings, the Hanfeizi would argue that fa is at the core of the state and that it ought 75 Hsiao-Po Wang and Leo S. Chang, The Philosophical Foundations of Han Fei\u00E2\u0080\u0099s Political Theory (Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii Press, 1986), 15. 76 Lai Yanyuan \u00E8\u00B3\u00B4\u00E7\u0082\u008E\u00E5\u0085\u0083 and Fu Wuguang \u00E5\u0082\u0085\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E5\u0085\u0089, Xinshi Hanfeizi \u00E6\u0096\u00B0\u00E9\u0087\u008B\u00E9\u009F\u0093\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E5\u00AD\u0090 (Taipei, Taiwan: Sanmin shuju, 2007), 17. 35 to be treated as the basic foundation of the ideal political order, which is precisely the kind of sentiment in Chapter 19 \u00E2\u0080\u009CShi Xie\u00E2\u0080\u009D (\u00E9\u00A3\u00BE\u00E9\u0082\u00AA, Rectifying Disorder): \u00E6\u0095\u0085\u00E5\u0085\u0088\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E5\u00B8\u00B8\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E6\u00B3\u0095\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E6\u009C\u00AC Therefore, the former kings deem the Dao to be the constant, and consider fa to be the root. 77 The notion of the Dao itself is not the primary point that is being expounded upon in the \u00E2\u0080\u009CWay of Rulership\u00E2\u0080\u009D chapter; it is considered to be the underlying principle in the political ideals that are being extolled here. For example, this chapter begins as follows: \u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0090\u00AC\u00E7\u0089\u00A9\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E5\u00A7\u008B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u0098\u00AF\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E7\u00B4\u0080\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u0098\u00AF\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E5\u00AE\u0088\u00E5\u00A7\u008B\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u009F\u00A5\u00E8\u0090\u00AC\u00E7\u0089\u00A9\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u00BA\u0090\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B2\u00BB\u00E7\u00B4\u0080\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u009F\u00A5\u00E5\u0096\u0084\u00E6\u0095\u0097 \u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E7\u00AB\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0082 As for the Dao, it is the beginning of the myriad things, [it is also] the standard of \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthis\u00E2\u0080\u009D and \u00E2\u0080\u009Cnot-this.\u00E2\u0080\u009D78 This is the reason the enlightened ruler preserves the beginning in order to know the source of the myriad beings, [and] regulates these standards in order to know the roots of good and bad. It is not particularly surprising to point out that the Hanfeizi based its entire philosophical structure on the notion of the Dao, as it seemed to be the common practice among contemporary intellectuals to variously define and ground their ideals on their own interpretations of this term. It is, however, intriguing to note how the Dao in this particular case is supposedly used by the enlightened ruler to understand the source of the myriad beings and to regulate the roots of goodness and wickedness. It is within this understanding, that is, that the Dao is at the source of all things, that the concept of fa can be interpreted. 77 Translations of the Hanfeizi in this section are my own. 78 Or \u00E2\u0080\u009Cright\u00E2\u0080\u009D and \u00E2\u0080\u009Cwrong,\u00E2\u0080\u009D in other words, making distinctions. 36 It is interesting to note, however, that while sage-king figures do appear in the Hanfeizi, they are more often than not depicted in a negative light. 79 Within the overall iconoclastic and antihistorical attitudes of these reformers who believed that \u00E2\u0080\u009CTo imitate antiquity is to be behind the times; to follow the status quo is to be bogged down in the face of changing circumstances.\u00E2\u0080\u009D 80 As circumstances change over time, the author of the Hanfeizi is unequivocal in emphasizing the importance of political practices corresponding to the needs of the times. Most importantly, the Hanfeizi is adamantly against the sage-kings because they were modeled upon the past, and it is made very clear that political practices ought to reflect current circumstances, appropriate to the actual needs of the state, and not merely be based on moralistic ideals that were formulated in the past where the situation was different. This point is made painfully clear in the Hanfeizi: Those who know nothing of proper government are certain to say: \u00E2\u0080\u0098Don\u00E2\u0080\u0099t change old ways! Don\u00E2\u0080\u0099t alter regular practices!\u00E2\u0080\u0099 As for changing or not changing, the sage is not interested. His only concern is proper government. This being so, whether or not he changes old ways or alters conventions depends on whether they will meet the present contingency. 81 That being said, that is not to say that the sage-king narratives are completely abandoned; rather, historical sage-king figures are now used as a way for the author of the Hanfeizi to critique and mock his ideological adversaries, most of whom use these very sage-kings to lend authority to their own arguments. This critique can be observed in the \u00E2\u0080\u009CEminence in Learning\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E9\u00A1\u00AF\u00E5\u00AD\u00B8 chapter: 79 \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B \u00E2\u0080\u009CSage-king\u00E2\u0080\u009D has a total of nine occurrences in the Hanfeizi, eight of them in a single chapter, the \u00E2\u0080\u009CShuoyi\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E8\u00AA\u00AA\u00E7\u0096\u0091. 80 Ames, Art of Rulership, 10\u00E2\u0080\u009311. 81 Ames, Art of Rulership, 11. 37 Confucius and Mozi both followed the ways of Yao and Shun, and though their practices differed, each claimed to be following the real Yao and Shun. But since we cannot call Yao and Shun back to life, who is to decide whether it is the Confucians or the Mohists who are telling the truth? \u00E2\u0080\u00A6If we cannot even decide which of the present versions of Confucian and Mohist doctrine are the genuine ones, how can we hope to scrutinize the ways of Yao and Shun, who lived three thousand years ago? \u00E2\u0080\u00A6Hence it is clear that those who claim to follow the ancient kings and to be able to describe with certainty the ways of Yao and Shun must be either fools or imposters. The learning of fools and imposters, doctrines that are motley and contradictory\u00E2\u0080\u0094such things as these the enlightened ruler will never accept.\u00E2\u0080\u009D82 While the critiques here are levied against the Confucians and the followers of the Mozi, they could very easily be applied to any author who employs the sage-king narratives for his own rhetorical purposes. It could be argued that the Hanfeizi in many ways maintains a similar rhetorical device within the narrative tradition by replacing the sage-kings with different terms that all ultimately mean \u00E2\u0080\u009Cenlightened ruler\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E4\u00B8\u00BB.83 Nonetheless, its disavowal of the sage-king figures, and its discrediting of the power of tradition and history is a revolutionary one. Even though the Hanfeizi seems to stay within the narrative tradition of using idealized figures to engage in intellectual debates with the other philosophers of the time; however, it is able to address and criticize the rival contemporary explications on political affairs by discrediting the historical sage-king figures. Clearly, the author of the Hanfeizi was quite cognizant of the different kinds of intellectual debate that were taking place at the time and used it to the advantage of his own political ideals. This kind of historical self-awareness on the part of the author of the Hanfeizi, while not unique, is especially 82 Han Feizi: Basic Writings, trans. Burton Watson (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 2003), 119\u00E2\u0080\u0093120. 83 In the Hanfeizi, the following phrases can be observed, with the number of individual occurrences in parentheses: \u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E4\u00B8\u00BB \u00E2\u0080\u009Cenlightened ruler\u00E2\u0080\u009D (94 occurrences), \u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E5\u0090\u009B \u00E2\u0080\u009Cenlightened monarch\u00E2\u0080\u009D (31 occurrences), \u00E6\u0098\u008E \u00E7\u008E\u008B \u00E2\u0080\u009Cenlightened king\u00E2\u0080\u009D (six occurrences), \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E4\u00B8\u00BB \u00E2\u0080\u009Csagacious ruler\u00E2\u0080\u009D (three occurrences), and \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E5\u0090\u009B \u00E2\u0080\u009Csagacious monarch\u00E2\u0080\u009D (one occurrence). 38 intriguing, as it allows for clearly defined positions of his own ideals and explications against those of the others; furthermore, it is possible to make very cynical criticisms of the other philosophers by incisively disputing their claims, while using their own terminology and concepts. Further elaborating on that point, Hanfeizi was also against the moralistic rhetoric of the many other authors of the time, claiming that much of their explication about proper virtues being absolutely necessary for good government was false. Its disdain for this kind of ideology can be extrapolated from the following passage: If someone were to go around telling people, \u00E2\u0080\u009CI can give you wisdom and long life!\u00E2\u0080\u009D, then the world would regard him as an imposter. Wisdom is a matter of man\u00E2\u0080\u0099s nature, and long life is a matter of fate, and neither\u00E2\u0080\u00A6can be got from others. \u00E2\u0080\u00A6Likewise, to try to teach people to be benevolent and righteous is the same as saying you can make them wise and long-lived. \u00E2\u0080\u00A6You may talk about the benevolence and righteousness of the former kings all you like, but it will not make your own state any better ordered\u00E2\u0080\u00A6.[the importance should be to] make your laws and regulations clear and your rewards and punishments certain... The enlightened ruler pays close attention to such aids to rule, and has little time for extolling the ancients. Therefore he does not talk about benevolence and righteousness. 84 At the outset, it is clear that the tone of this passage is quite cynical and profoundly realistic. Not only does it liken many of its contemporary authors to imposters, but it essentially discounts their explications as not actually effective at all in terms of bringing about order and proper governance. Similarly, the author also reveals his basic distrust of the traditions from the past and of the sage-king figures whose virtues were extolled at great length, further emphasizing his claim that government policies ought to reflect the realities of the time and not merely rely on beguiling words and history. As a whole, the 84 Hanfeizi, \u00E2\u0080\u009CEminence in Learning\u00E2\u0080\u009D, trans. Watson, 128. 39 iconoclastic and perhaps even revolutionary undertones of the political ideals of the Hanfeizi are still within the same kind of rhetorical structure as the sage-king narratives that he discounts. But in this case, he has merely replaced the sage-king figure with an idealized \u00E2\u0080\u009Cenlightened ruler\u00E2\u0080\u009D and presents this figure in a way that is both convincing and practical, especially to the rulers who were presumed to be his primary audience. It could be argued that these kinds of political ideals reflect the kind of realpolitik that was already the norm among the warring states at this time, not only fully justifying the increasingly powerful bureaucratizing state apparatus, but also giving the authoritarian rulers the kinds of ideological legitimization needed for exerting control over the other vested interests who had traditionally competed with or even supplanted the rulers. For instance, as Ames points out, in the Hanfeizi, one of the greatest obstacles to the ruler\u00E2\u0080\u0099s fully exercising his power is the established order of ministers and the hereditary privilege of the powerful families who dominate the courts; the author\u00E2\u0080\u0099s principles would effectively render this establishment obsolete. 85 2.4 Sage-Kings as Conscious Fabrications It is questionable what, in the minds of these thinkers, the sage-kings were or might have been like in reality; what truly mattered was that these were figures that contemporary rulers could aspire to become, by manifesting or cultivating specific qualities that these thinkers attributed to the sage-kings. To take this point even further, some scholars have even argued that \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe revered sages of early Chinese antiquity were in all likelihood the inventions of authors from the Warring States and Han periods;\u00E2\u0080\u009D that 85 Ames, Art of Rulership, 9\u00E2\u0080\u009310. 40 is to say, they were artificial devices constructed consciously to further arguments and to lend legitimacy to the political views of those authors who employed them. 86 Similarly, even some of these authors recognized that, by and large, the sage-kings were often used as dialectic devices in their debates with one another in order to secure a sense of legitimacy. This was the case in a rather sarcastic passage of the Huainanzi \u00E6\u00B7\u00AE\u00E5\u008D\u0097\u00E5\u00AD\u0090, in which the author revealed that \u00E2\u0080\u009C[t]he average modern person holds the ancient in high esteem...Those who work out methods must attribute them to Shennong and Huangdi, and only then will they be admitted into the debate.\u00E2\u0080\u009D87 In other words, it was clear even to authors at the time that in order to be able to participate in the ongoing debates, they had to resort to using concepts such as the sage-kings in their discourse, even if their ideas originally had nothing to do with these mythical figures. Thus, if the same ideal rulers, the sage-kings, were to appear and be depicted in the texts of different authors, it would be inaccurate to presume that they would be one and the same. Reflective of the historical context of the time, they were only the same insofar as their names were identical; even their origins might not have been the same sources. The ways the sage-kings have been so differently characterized by different texts are representative of two things. First of all, the characteristics and achievements of the sage-kings differed from author to author in order to reflect what they themselves thought were the qualities that ideal rulers ought to exhibit. Secondly, these texts were, in all likelihood, written at different times, in different localities, and certainty by different groups of intellectuals who were active during the conflict-prone centuries of the Warring 86 Puett, \u00E2\u0080\u009CSages, Ministers, and Rebels,\u00E2\u0080\u009D 427. 87 Csikszentmihalyi and Nylan, \u00E2\u0080\u009CConstructing Lineages,\u00E2\u0080\u009D 97. 41 States period. What they shared was a similar cultural heritage that was composed of religious and mythological thought and a belief that there were solutions to what they perceived to be the greatest problems that plagued their harsh realities. All in all, it is unlikely that the inherent discrepancies that exist between these different political ideals can be easily integrated. Despite the fact that these sage-kings were all perceived to be the same mythological figures from times past, the reality was that they were created from completely different contexts. Nevertheless, precisely because of the existence of these inherent differences, they have become an effective mirror from which we can gain insight into not only the circumstances that led to the formation of these texts but also into the ideas that they attempted to transmit. This process of textual and conceptual evolution continued throughout the entire Warring States period, and it was not until the early imperial eras that it comparatively slowed down. Though even then, it did not completely stabilize and become canonical until much later. 88 Most scholars generally recognize these inherent disagreements between the natures of the sage-kings as postulated by different authors. Some scholars like Graham, Lewis, and Csikszentmihalyi and Nylan go so far as to claim that these authors were consciously aware that they were attributing characteristics to sage-king figures for their own rhetorical purposes. Upon further investigation of this claim, it is difficult to find direct references in the texts themselves where the authors admit that they were merely using the sage-king as a convenient way to put moral authority behind their political 88 Ibid., 99. 42 ideals. Nonetheless, it is possible to find many critiques, especially in later Warring States texts like the Hanfeizi, of the fact that different authors will claim to represent the true vision of the sage-kings, yet all of them are different. This being the case, leading contemporary scholarship has attempted to deal with these discrepancies differently. Some, like Lewis in Sanctioned Violence in Early China, following in the footsteps of eminent scholars like Marcel Granet, Gu Jiegang, Bernhard Karlgren, and Henri Maspero, systematically organize and reconstruct particular sage- king myths in order to analyze how they were a part of larger Warring States narratives that sought both to rationalize and to legitimize the changing nature of sanctioned state violence. 89 Puett, however, argues that attempts to extrapolate deeper meaning from reconstructed myths of the sage-kings is problematic, mostly because they oversimplify and even obscure some of the more contentious and contradictory narratives. 90 While they disagree in the particularities of their methodologies, as a whole, it is clear that scholars recognize that these narratives did indeed change over time and that the scholars\u00E2\u0080\u0099 divergent approaches merely reflect a different way of extrapolating the significance of these changes from the texts themselves. Having roughly traced the origins of the sage-kings and the development of philosophical narratives that revolved around these mythical figures, it is important to note that much of their evolution took place not only due to the changing political circumstances of the centralizing states, but also especially as a result of the interactions and reactions between different philosophical and political ideologies. I believe that it is 89 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 165\u00E2\u0080\u0093212. 90 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation, 99\u00E2\u0080\u0093100. 43 because of this latter point that there exist many inherent contradictions within the broader problematique of sage-king narratives. I do not believe that the most important task for scholars is to attempt to reconstruct these myths, nor is it to accurately pinpoint the exact origins of these tales, at least not without some collaborative work with archaeological sources. I agree with Puett in his evaluation of this situation, in that the more important task is actively to question and redefine our interpretation of these narratives in order to gain a more multifaceted understanding both of these texts in the greater scheme of Warring States intellectual history and also of the kinds of political interests and concerns that gave rise to those very ideals in the first place. It is with this in mind, then, that I next turn to analyze in a very preliminary way some particular narratives that form common threads between different Warring States texts, which deal with different themes of political importance. 44 3. Sage-King Narratives and Political Concerns: Two Cases Despite the abundance of textual sources and the emphasis of scholars who focus on the mythological accounts of the past as enshrined in these Warring States texts, it should be pointed out that these narratives about the sage-kings are largely hypothesized in our understanding of both history and the development of philosophy in early China. Much of how the sage-kings were depicted in these texts reveal particular concerns that their authors with respect to different aspects of the changing political circumstances. The different perspectives and goals of these authors, all attempting to claim the right to define and present the sage-kings in their own ways, gave rise to the problem of contradictions and incompatibilities between myths about the same figures. For instance, as Puett points out, \u00E2\u0080\u009Cin some narratives acts of creation are ascribed to Huangdi, while in others they are ascribed to ministers or rebels;\u00E2\u0080\u009D the important thing in these cases, then, is not to find ways to make the inherent contradictions fit within the mythological model and dismiss those that don\u00E2\u0080\u0099t fit as merely erroneous.91 Instead, under the hypothesis that many of these Warring States narratives are \u00E2\u0080\u009Cretellings of a limited number of stories\u00E2\u0080\u009D that cover different themes that mattered to their authors, the focus should be on questioning and analyzing which figures were employed, what actions have been attributed to them, and what this reveals about the contexts in which they were written. This practice of attributing characteristics to \u00E2\u0080\u009Chistorical\u00E2\u0080\u009D figures was common practice among these authors. As D. C. Lau points out, each intellectual tradition often had \u00E2\u0080\u009Cits favourites among the ancient kings\u00E2\u0080\u00A6 [furthermore, these] ancient personages 91 Puett, Ambivalence of Creation , 97. 45 were made concrete embodiments of moral qualities. \u00E2\u0080\u00A6Yao was the embodiment of kingly virtue, and Shun, beside being a sage king was also the embodiment of filial virtue.\u00E2\u0080\u009D92 The differences among these texts in the portrayal of particular narratives that involve sage-king figures reveal a fundamental malleability in their construction as rhetorical devices. Furthermore, the fact that there exists a much greater level of complexity also reveals particular political and ideological concerns that were significant to their authors. To this end, I will examine two sample narratives that correspond to significant issues regarding the formation of human civilization and the state, as well as political legitimacy in term of succession, with different interpretations. The first narrative of interest is that of the great flood and its role in the conceptual formation of the triumph and birth of human civilization against unrelenting natural forces, through the sage-king Yu. The second will deal with the question of legitimate ways for the transfer of political authority, which in essence raises questions about whether hereditary or meritocratic principles would take precedence in not only matters of royal succession but also of office holding, through the narrative of the sage-kings Yao and Shun. 3.1 Flood Taming Narratives of Yu and Human Civilization The tales of Yu and the great flood are some of the earliest that have been recorded in written documents that predate the Warring States period. As Lewis points out, citing Gu Jiegang, \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthere are no less than six references to Yu in Zhou [Book of Odes] 92 Mencius, trans. D.C. Lau (London, UK : Penguin Group, 2004),187. 46 \u00E8\u00A9\u00A9\u00E7\u00B6\u0093 that date from between ca. 1000 and 600 B.C.,\u00E2\u0080\u009D and similarly, there are even more references to Yu in the Book of Documents \u00E6\u009B\u00B8\u00E7\u00B6\u0093, where even two chapters have been named after this sage-king figure. 93 Like most of the other myths that make up much of our understanding of how the early Chinese conceptualized their world, however, these narratives of the great flood and its taming by the great Yu are scattered and not at all systematic. That being said, a general commonality among many of these narratives, as reconstructed by scholars like Allan, is that they function largely as myths about creation and most importantly as historical accounts of fashioning a particularly humanistic order from the primal chaos, as a way for demarcations to be drawn both literally in the world and also reflected in the organization of human society. 94 These myths, then, could be interpreted, on the one hand, as fundamental for cosmogonic conceptualizations, especially addressing the origins of human society and the political organizations that are inherently required as part of that society\u00E2\u0080\u0099s development. On the other hand, the myths could be interpreted as sanctions for that very political authority; they attempt to give philosophical justification for the warring states that were aggressively changing their relationship with the land through dramatic transformations and through exerting direct control over both the land and those who lived on it. 95 Nonetheless, depending on the perspectives of the authors who adapted these narratives for their own uses, these accounts of the flood and the taming of the flood continued to evolve over time. In this vein, I would like to compare earlier accounts 93 Lewis, Flood Myths, 28. 94 Sarah Allan, The Way of Water and the Sprouts of Virtue (Albany, NY: State University of New York, 1997), 39\u00E2\u0080\u009341. 95 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 169. 47 of sage-king Yu and the taming of the flood with later accounts in the Mencius, where tales about human efforts in habilitating the primal world of chaos evolved into an analogy for an internalized process of self-cultivation. As mentioned earlier, even though some of the earliest recorded references to Yu as the tamer of the great flood can be found in the Book of Odes, many of these references date to a time prior to the Warring States period. However, these passages merely refer to the figure known as Yu, and some associate him with the flood without offering any explanation or details about his actual deeds and achievements. Actual accounts and proper narratives can only be found in the Book of Documents, and as Lewis suspects, they were most likely Warring States compositions and depict the problem of the great flood. 96 Nonetheless, the significance of the evolution of the flood controlling narratives between the earlier and later accounts is twofold. First of all, it is clear by the examples in the Book of Odes that narratives regarding the great flood and the sage-king Yu existed even before the dawn of the Warring States period; the only issue is that it may be impossible to find out what those narratives entailed without further evidence. Secondly, it matters not whether forms of these narratives recorded during the Warring States period were true to their earlier counterparts, at least for the current inquiry, because it is sufficient to compare those narratives with other versions also composed during the same period in order to gain a better understanding of the intent of their respective authors. Most of the accomplishments of Yu were depicted in the \u00E2\u0080\u009CTributes of Yu\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E8\u00B2\u00A2 96 Lewis, Flood Myths, 28\u00E2\u0080\u009329. 48 chapter of the Book of Documents, and one particularly telling passage as translated by Lewis is as follows: \u00E2\u0080\u009CYu [divided] the land, he followed the mountains and cut down the trees, to establish the highest mountains and the greatest rivers.\u00E2\u0080\u009D97 In this passage, it can be understood that the author of this text likens the taming of the flood by Yu to practices of domesticating the physical landscape, effectively shaping it in such a way as to be hospitable for human society. Furthermore, it presents a very particular kind of relationship between humanity and nature. It frames nature as something that requires conscious effort to control and cultivate, and at the same time, these natural forces, as represented by the \u00E2\u0080\u009Chighest mountains and the greatest rivers,\u00E2\u0080\u009D ought to be clearly separated from human society. The chapter continues on to name and describe the various geographical features that were demarcated by Yu in his attempt to tame the flood and, in the process, to settle the lands. The chapter finally concludes with a summary of Yu\u00E2\u0080\u0099s accomplishments in the following passage: The nine provinces formed a unity, with the usable land to the four edges of the earth all having been made into habitations. The nine mountains had roads carved through their forests and offerings presented to them. The nine rivers were dredged and flowing, while the nine marshes had all been embanked. Everything within the four seas converged [at the capital]. The six treasures [all natural resources] were all completely put in order. They myriad soils [of the different regions] had all been correctly evaluated, so as to scrupulously imposed a levy on resources. He had completely modeled the three soil types to perfect the levies of the central states. 98 97 Lewis, Flood Myths, 30\u00E2\u0080\u009331.\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E6\u0095\u00B7\u00E5\u009C\u009F\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E9\u009A\u00A8\u00E5\u00B1\u00B1\u00E5\u0088\u008A\u00E6\u009C\u00A8\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u00A5\u00A0\u00E9\u00AB\u0098\u00E5\u00B1\u00B1\u00E5\u00A4\u00A7\u00E5\u00B7\u009D\u00E3\u0080\u0082 98 Lewis, Flood Myths, 32. \u00E4\u00B9\u009D\u00E5\u00B7\u009E\u00E6\u0094\u00B8\u00E5\u0090\u008C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u009B\u009B\u00E9\u009A\u00A9\u00E6\u0097\u00A2\u00E5\u00AE\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00B9\u009D\u00E5\u00B1\u00B1\u00E5\u0088\u008A\u00E6\u0097\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00B9\u009D\u00E5\u00B7\u009D\u00E6\u00BB\u008C\u00E6\u00BA\u0090\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00B9\u009D\u00E6\u00BE\u00A4\u00E6\u0097\u00A2\u00E9\u0099\u0082\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u009B\u009B\u00E6\u00B5\u00B7\u00E6\u009C\u0083\u00E5\u0090\u008C\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u0085\u00AD\u00E5\u00BA\u009C \u00E5\u00AD\u0094\u00E4\u00BF\u00AE\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u00BA\u00B6\u00E5\u009C\u009F\u00E4\u00BA\u00A4\u00E6\u00AD\u00A3\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u008E\u008E\u00E6\u0085\u008E\u00E8\u00B2\u00A1\u00E8\u00B3\u00A6\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u0092\u00B8\u00E5\u0089\u0087\u00E4\u00B8\u0089\u00E5\u00A3\u00A4\u00E6\u0088\u0090\u00E8\u00B3\u00A6\u00E3\u0080\u0082 49 In this passage, the basic units of political organization are clear, as All-under-Heaven is now divided into the nine provinces, a division which still had a certain ideological significance in the minds of the Warring States authors, even if in reality these nine provinces no longer corresponded to the actual territories under the control of the various warring states. Nonetheless, the fact that \u00E2\u0080\u009Cthe nine provinces formed a unity\u00E2\u0080\u009D is not insignificant, for it holds the connotation that regardless of divided political realities, the world ought to be a single unit, under the rightful ruler as the Son of Heaven. The subsequent sections about road building, river dredging, and marsh embanking again are continuations of the narrative that the natural landscape requires human control. Finally, perhaps what is even more interesting than the physical management of the lands is the evaluation of resources and the measuring of \u00E2\u0080\u009Csoil types,\u00E2\u0080\u009D presumably for purposes of taxation. Again, while a more profound analysis of this observation is outside the purviews of my research, the fact remains that this discourse represents a particular kind of politically motivated narrative that not only legitimizes the state in exerting absolute control over the land but also gives it the kind of ideological justification for taxation. It does this especially by giving these practices authoritative power by associating them with \u00E2\u0080\u009Chistory,\u00E2\u0080\u009D even if in reality these kinds of policies might not at all be what were practised in the times of Yu. The political implications of the narrative of the flood taming by Yu can be interpreted even further, according to Lewis, as it \u00E2\u0080\u009Cprovided a mythical prototype for the irrigation and water control projects of the Warring States period.\u00E2\u0080\u009D One of the major technological developments during this time was the creation of various hydraulics projects, which allowed for increases in areas that could now be both habitable and 50 suitable for agriculture. 99 A similar depiction of the same narrative can be seen in the Mencius, where Shun is portrayed as employing Yu to tame the uncontrollable floods that have rampaged since the time of Yao: In the time of Yao, the water reversed its natural course, flooding the central regions and the reptiles made their homes there, depriving the people of a settled life. In low-lying regions, people lived in nests; in high regions, they lived in caves\u00E2\u0080\u00A6Yu was entrusted with the task of controlling it. He led the flood water into the seas by cutting channels for it in the ground and drove the reptiles into grassy marshes. \u00E2\u0080\u00A6Obstacles receded and the birds and beast harmful to men were annihilated. Only then were the people able to level the ground and live on it. 100 The first important observation that should be made here is the fact that the Mencius makes it very clear that the great flood is a result of the water not acting in its natural course, which is a sentiment that did not exist in the earlier accounts of the flood in the Book of Documents. Another interesting observation is the fact that due to the unnatural flood waters, human beings are reduced to living like animals, in nests and caves, which again reinforces a particular kind of moralistic ideal, that human beings are distinct from animals and that that distinction is of the utmost importance to maintain. The coming of the flood has washed away all of those important distinguishing factors. The inherent importance attributed to these artificial boundaries will be seen in the next passage. The flood narrative is repeated elsewhere with a slightly different emphasis: In the time of Yao, the Empire was not yet settled. The Flood still raged 99 Lewis, Flood Myths, 19; Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 165. 100 Mencius III.B.9, trans. Lau, 72. \u00E7\u0095\u00B6\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u0099\u0082\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E9\u0080\u0086\u00E8\u00A1\u008C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B0\u00BE\u00E6\u00BF\u00AB\u00E6\u0096\u00BC\u00E4\u00B8\u00AD\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E8\u009B\u0087\u00E9\u00BE\u008D\u00E5\u00B1\u0085\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B0\u0091\u00E7\u0084\u00A1\u00E6\u0089\u0080\u00E5\u00AE\u009A\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E5\u00B7\u00A2\u00EF\u00BC\u008C \u00E4\u00B8\u008A\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E7\u0087\u009F\u00E7\u00AA\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E6\u008E\u0098\u00E5\u009C\u00B0\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E6\u00B3\u00A8\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u00B5\u00B7\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E9\u00A9\u0085\u00E8\u009B\u0087\u00E9\u00BE\u008D\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E6\u0094\u00BE\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E8\u008F\u00B9\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E9\u009A\u00AA\u00E9\u0098\u00BB\u00E6\u0097\u00A2\u00E9\u0081\u00A0\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E9\u00B3\u00A5\u00E7\u008D\u00B8\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E5\u00AE\u00B3\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E6\u00B6\u0088\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E7\u0084\u00B6\u00E5\u00BE\u008C\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E5\u00BE\u0097\u00E5\u00B9\u00B3\u00E5\u009C\u009F\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00B1\u0085 \u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E3\u0080\u0082 51 unchecked, inundating the Empire\u00E2\u0080\u00A6Yu dredged the Nine Rivers, cleared the Courses of the Chi and the T\u00E2\u0080\u0099a to channel the water into the Sea\u00E2\u0080\u00A6 Only then were the people of the Central Kingdoms able to find food for themselves. [Then] Hou Chi taught the people how to farm and grown the five kinds of grain. When these ripened, the people multiplied. This is the way of the common people: once they have a full belly and warm clothes on the back they degenerate to the level of animals if they are allowed to lead idle lives, without education and discipline. This gave the sage King further cause for concern and so he appointed Hsieh as the Minister of Education whose duty was to teach the people human relationships: love between father and son, duty between ruler and subject, distinction between husband and wife, precedence of the old over the young, and faith between friends.\u00E2\u0080\u009D101 In this second passage, the beginning seems to be essentially the same as the other passage, except that in this case, the emphasis is really on the proceeding developments in human civilization that Yu\u00E2\u0080\u0099s taming of the flood made possible. Not only were the people finally able to fend for themselves, but they were also finally able to practice agriculture. Perhaps the next point is even more intriguing, as the Mencius points out that there is nothing that truly distinguishes humans from animals, as both are likely to be content to be fed and be comfortable, unless humans are taught, presumably, the virtues of the sage-kings. This is an interesting point, as it emphasizes again the division between human civilization and animalistic nature, and it stresses that what truly distinguishes the one from the other are the teachings of the sages, much as sage-king Yu was able to physically divide the world and demarcate the boundaries between the human and the inhuman. This is where Mencius\u00E2\u0080\u0099s philosophical ideals are then introduced as the crucial 101 Mencius IIIA4, trans. Lau 59\u00E2\u0080\u009360. \u00E7\u0095\u00B6\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u0099\u0082\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E7\u008C\u00B6\u00E6\u009C\u00AA\u00E5\u00B9\u00B3\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B4\u00AA\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E6\u00A9\u00AB\u00E6\u00B5\u0081\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B0\u00BE\u00E6\u00BF\u00AB\u00E6\u0096\u00BC\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E7\u0096\u008F\u00E4\u00B9\u009D\u00E6\u00B2\u00B3\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E7\u0080\u00B9 \u00E6\u00BF\u009F\u00E6\u00BC\u00AF\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E6\u00B3\u00A8\u00E8\u00AB\u00B8\u00E6\u00B5\u00B7\u00E2\u0080\u00A6\u00E7\u0084\u00B6\u00E5\u00BE\u008C\u00E4\u00B8\u00AD\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E5\u008F\u00AF\u00E5\u00BE\u0097\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E9\u00A3\u009F\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u0090\u008E\u00E7\u00A8\u00B7\u00E6\u0095\u0099\u00E6\u00B0\u0091\u00E7\u00A8\u00BC\u00E7\u00A9\u00A1\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u00A8\u00B9\u00E8\u0097\u009D\u00E4\u00BA\u0094\u00E7\u00A9\u0080\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BA\u0094\u00E7\u00A9\u0080\u00E7\u0086\u009F\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E6\u00B0\u0091\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E8\u0082\u00B2\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00EF\u00BC\u008C \u00E9\u00A3\u00BD\u00E9\u00A3\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E7\u0085\u0096\u00E8\u00A1\u00A3\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E9\u0080\u00B8\u00E5\u00B1\u0085\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E7\u0084\u00A1\u00E6\u0095\u0099\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u0089\u0087\u00E8\u00BF\u0091\u00E6\u0096\u00BC\u00E7\u00A6\u00BD\u00E7\u008D\u00B8\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E6\u0086\u0082\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BD\u00BF\u00E5\u00A5\u0091\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E5\u008F\u00B8\u00E5\u00BE\u0092\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u0095\u0099\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E5\u0080\u00AB\u00EF\u00BC\u009A\u00E7\u0088\u00B6\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E8\u00A6\u00AA\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E6\u009C\u0089 \u00E7\u00BE\u00A9\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u00A4\u00AB\u00E5\u00A9\u00A6\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E5\u0088\u00A5\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E9\u0095\u00B7\u00E5\u00B9\u00BC\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E5\u00BA\u008F\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u009C\u008B\u00E5\u008F\u008B\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E4\u00BF\u00A1\u00E3\u0080\u0082 52 factor that will protect humans from falling back into being no better than animals. Namely, the proper human relationships between the following: father and son, ruler and subject, husband and wife, the old and the young, and finally between friends. The proper maintenance of these social relationships is necessary for the maintenance of this distinctively humanistic order, and this reveals the kind of importance that the author of the Mencius places on this specific ideal. It is in the vein of this kind of great flood narrative, then, that we find that the Mencius is able to port a familiar imagery, using it to deemphasize the more overtly political aspects of the rhetoric, instead focussing on how it can be applied to a more personal self-cultivation of virtues and to a discussion about human nature. This is the situation here in the following passage: [Bo Gui] said, \u00E2\u0080\u009CIn dealing with water I am better than Yu.\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E2\u0080\u009CYou are mistaken,\u00E2\u0080\u009D said Mencius. \u00E2\u0080\u009CIn dealing with water, Yu followed the natural tendency of water. Hence he emptied the water into the Four Seas. Now you empty the water into the neighbouring states. When water goes counter to its course, it is descried as a \u00E2\u0080\u0098deluge\u00E2\u0080\u0099, in other words, a \u00E2\u0080\u0098flood\u00E2\u0080\u0099, and floods are detested by the benevolent man. You are mistaken, my good sir.\u00E2\u0080\u009D102 Superficially, this passage can still be considered part of the flood taming narrative, especially extolling the virtues of sage-king Yu. Nonetheless, a much more telling moralistic tone is exhibited by the author of the Mencius in the depicting of water going \u00E2\u0080\u009Ccounter to its course,\u00E2\u0080\u009D as the proper flow of water has now taken a much deeper moralistic connotation, representing human nature. This analogy is made in another chapter when the Mencius argues that \u00E2\u0080\u009CIt is certainly the case\u00E2\u0080\u00A6that water does not show any preference for either east or west, but does it show the same indifference to high and 102 Mencius VI.B.11, trans. Lau, 141. \u00E7\u0099\u00BD\u00E5\u009C\u00AD\u00E6\u009B\u00B0\u00EF\u00BC\u009A\u00E3\u0080\u008C\u00E4\u00B8\u00B9\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u00B2\u00BB\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E6\u0084\u0088\u00E6\u0096\u00BC\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E3\u0080\u008D\u00E5\u00AD\u009F\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E6\u009B\u00B0\u00EF\u00BC\u009A\u00E3\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E9\u0081\u008E\u00E7\u009F\u00A3\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u00B2\u00BB\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00EF\u00BC\u008C \u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u0098\u00AF\u00E6\u0095\u0085\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E5\u009B\u009B\u00E6\u00B5\u00B7\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E5\u00A3\u0091\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BB\u008A\u00E5\u0090\u00BE\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E9\u0084\u00B0\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E5\u00A3\u0091\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E9\u0080\u0086\u00E8\u00A1\u008C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u00AC\u0082\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u00B4\u009A\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u00B4\u009A\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B4\u00AA\u00E6\u00B0\u00B4\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BB\u0081\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E4\u00B9\u008B \u00E6\u0089\u0080\u00E6\u0083\u00A1\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u0090\u00BE\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E9\u0081\u008E\u00E7\u009F\u00A3\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E3\u0080\u008D 53 low? Human nature is good just as water seeks low ground. There is no man who is not good; there is no water that does not flow downwards.\u00E2\u0080\u009D103 Taken together, then, these two passages demonstrate the kind of evolution that the narrative of the great flood underwent; it indeed was changed and was used by the author of the Mencius to assert a particular philosophical point that was most likely not previously expressed. It is difficult to say with absolute certainty whether or not the author deliberately associated the taming of the flood to the particular methods of moral self-cultivation that he was advocating, or deliberately associated the kind of \u00E2\u0080\u009Cunnatural\u00E2\u0080\u009D practices of his intellectual rivals with the chaotic primordial flood. As Lewis so incisively points out, in order to understand the profound significance of the great flood narrative within the intellectual context of early China in general, it is necessary to understand that \u00E2\u0080\u009CAt every level, the early Chinese perceived the threat of a looming chaos, and argued for the necessity of maintaining clear lines of division to prevent a collapse back into this void.\u00E2\u0080\u009D104 These concerns about division and separation can be observed in questions about the following issues: the inner and outer self; fundamental familial relationships, man-woman, father-son, elder-younger, ruler-ruled, and so forth; and especially also the living and the dead. 105 The sage-king figures (or in the case of the Hanfeizi, the enlightened ruler) too, it could be argued, played a significant role in this entire discourse, as they were the ones that initially established the boundaries, the ones who succeeded in maintaining these separations and ensuring that human order did not give way to natural chaos. As a whole, especially during the Warring States period, just 103 Mencius VI.A.2 , trans. Lau, 122. 104 Lewis, Flood Myths, 21. 105 Ibid. 54 as the changing political circumstances affected the state-society relations, the sage-king ideals too were employed by these intellectuals who attempted to interpret the changes they witnessed within their own philosophical frameworks. 3.2 Yao and Shun: Narratives of Rightful Succession or Usurpation Another set of narratives that can be dated to as early as those about the great flood are those regarding the abdication of sage-king Yao to the virtuous Shun, and eventually the abdication of Shun to Yu. As Allan points out, two closely related ideas have traditionally been interpreted as Chinese dynastic history: namely, the cyclical nature of the rise and fall of dynasties as well as the political legitimacy of the ruling dynasty being linked to the so-called Mandate of Heaven and its transferability. 106 This is another important fundamental issue within the development of early Chinese political philosophy, because in these narratives about legitimate political successions, there is an inherent tension between the principles of hereditary rights and the meritocratic rule by virtue. Despite the fact of the violent overthrow of the Shang by the Zhou, and the equally violent replacement of inept rulers, the Zhou royal house managed to remain Sons of Heaven for well over six centuries. 107 During this time, even though the Zhou no longer held the kind of power and influence over the other states that it had once held, none of the rebels who challenged the Zhou claimed to have the Mandate of Heaven, nor did any of the regional lords replace the Zhou until 256 BCE, when the Qin state finally extinguished their rule. 106 Allan, Heir and the Sage, 4\u00E2\u0080\u00935. 107 Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire, 58. 55 That being said, even though the various warring states did not see the Zhou royal lineage posing any real threat in their conflicts with one another, questions of legitimate succession were nonetheless important issues that many of the Warring States texts attempted to address through the sage-king narratives of Yao and Shun. One possible explanation for this interest could very well be associated with the partition of the state of Jin \u00E6\u0099\u0089 in 403 BCE by its vassal states of Zhao \u00E8\u00B6\u0099, Wei \u00E9\u00AD\u008F, and Han \u00E9\u009F\u0093; as well as the usurpation of the Qi \u00E9\u00BD\u008A state by one of its ministerial families, the Tian \u00E7\u0094\u00B0. Thus, it could be argued that these texts also reflected the historical context and political climate of the time, with the hereditary principle for political succession being subverted, as well as the increasing popularity of meritocratic principles for political appointments and perhaps even for succession. Within the scope of my research, it is not possible adequately to address all of the issues that can be extrapolated from this topic; it has already been analyzed to a much more thorough extent by Allan in her work. My focus instead will be on particular narratives about succession in relation to sage-king figures, in the attempt to understand the kinds of political concerns of those authors who explicate either for or against the theory of succession by the virtuous. The willingness of Yao in yielding the throne to Shun, the most virtuous and capable of his minsters, and the subsequent abdication of Shun in favour of Yu for the same reasons have been extolled by later Confucians as demonstrative of these rulers\u00E2\u0080\u0099 virtues, for their being completely selfless and for caring for the public good rather than for their own interests. As Lewis points out, in the act of giving up their positions as ruler 56 to the most capable, both of these sage-kings \u00E2\u0080\u009Cdefined the character of public rule by setting it apart from the claims of kinship and inheritance;\u00E2\u0080\u009D this, too, would later be used as the justification for the transfer of political authority between different dynasties. 108 For instance, regarding the issue of Yao\u00E2\u0080\u0099s selection of Shun to be his successor, it is depicted thusly in the Analects: Yao said, Oh, you Shun! The orderly succession of Heaven now rests upon your shoulders. Hold faithfully to the mean. If those within the Four Seas should fall into hardship and poverty, Heaven\u00E2\u0080\u0099s emoluments will be cut off from you. Shun charged Yu with the same words. 109 Two major ideas can be extracted from this passage: firstly, the idea of allowing for the worthy to succeed, and secondly, how to maintain Heaven\u00E2\u0080\u0099s good will by guarding the people from \u00E2\u0080\u009Chardship and poverty.\u00E2\u0080\u009D There remain ambiguities with regards to the question of succession, but it is very clear from looking at this passage what the perceived role of the sage-kings was, namely, to safeguard the interests of the people. Yao\u00E2\u0080\u0099s yielding the throne to Shun, who was perceived to be the most capable, created a sense of historical precedent that allowed for those deemed worthy to claim political power or legitimized the practice of supplanting the ruling dynasty with another. 110 That being the case, there is an inherent complication in this entire narrative that Allan addresses and which I find intriguing, regarding the proper transfer of political authority. By looking at the four sample sets of nonhereditary transfers of power between the supposed reign of Shun and that of King Wu, two of them (Yao to Shun, and Shun to Yu) were \u00E2\u0080\u009Ccharacterized by a gesture of ritual abdication and the possible absence of 108 Lewis, Sanctioned Violence, 165. 109 Analects, 7.1, trans. Slingerland, 231. 110 Allan, Heir and the Sage, 27\u00E2\u0080\u009333. 57 violence,\u00E2\u0080\u009D while in comparison, the transfer between Jie \u00E6\u00A1\u0080 and Tang \u00E6\u00B9\u00AF as well as between Zhou \u00E7\u00B4\u0082 and King Wu \u00E2\u0080\u009Cmust include some element of force and never a ritual abdication,\u00E2\u0080\u009D in addition to a certain degree of moral righteousness on the part of the successors. 111 Thus, it could be argued that while the philosophy behind the nonhereditary transfer of power remains the same, that is to say, the morally righteous and the virtuous have the right to succeed to the throne, the circumstances and perspectives are completely different between the former two cases and the latter two cases. In the former, these abdications were initiated by the ruler currently in power, as is presumably his prerogative as a representative of Heaven; in the latter, the usurpers claim to have the will of Heaven and use force to contest those very claims. According to the Mencius, however, it is not at all the current ruler who decides, but Heaven. Thus, even though both Yao and Shun chose the most worthy amongst their ministers, while Yu\u00E2\u0080\u0099s successor was his own son, the Mencius would argue that they all followed the exact same principle of succession by the worthy. This is depicted in this passage: \u00E2\u0080\u009CIf Heaven wished to give the Empire to a good and wise man, then it should be given to a good and wise man. But if Heaven wished to give it to the son, then it should be given to the son,\u00E2\u0080\u009D who was presumably also virtuous.112 Even though these narratives about succession are centred on the rulers and Sons of Heaven, it was probably more likely that these ideas of giving offices based on merit and not on familial inheritance were being applied much more broadly to government posts in general. This was something that the Mozi emphasized greatly, as \u00E2\u0080\u009C[t]he ancient 111 Ibid., 54. 112 Mencius V.A.6, trans. Lau, 106. 58 sage-kings were not partisan toward fathers and brothers; did not lean toward the noble and the rich and did not favor beauty. If there were men of worth they promoted them.\u00E2\u0080\u009D113 As a part of the overall evolution of these narratives during the Warring States, however, the concept of \u00E2\u0080\u009Cvirtuous abdication\u00E2\u0080\u009D on the one hand and \u00E2\u0080\u009Crighteous rebellion\u00E2\u0080\u009D on the other became embedded in the political discourses of the time through the use of the sage-kings. 114 That being said, even as Yao and Shun became fully entrenched within the Warring States intellectual consciousness, there was never a systemic inclusion of these accounts of abdication among all of the texts, while some of them openly ridicule the idea and discount it altogether. Furthermore, as both Pines and Graham point out, any kind of discussion regarding nonhereditary succession in these texts must be treated with care and much sensitivity by the authors themselves, as it effectively challenges the established norms of inheritance and is subversive. Nonetheless, this is where embedding such radical ideals could be safe within historical narratives like this, as they are considered merely tales and pose no real threat to the established political order. Just as there were Warring States texts that extolled the virtuous Yao and Shun for yielding their thrones for greater public good, not all agreed. As Lau points out, \u00E2\u0080\u009Caccording to the Bamboo Annals, Shun imprisoned Yao and Ch\u00E2\u0080\u0099i [the son of Yu] put Yi to death.\u00E2\u0080\u009D115 The accuracy and authenticity of these accounts aside, the fact of the matter is that if we take the depiction of the succession narrative as interpreted by the Bamboo Annals into consideration, then not only was Shun hardly the virtuous sage-king at all, but he was a master political manipulator who managed to force his ruler to abdicate in 113 Mozi Chapter 9, trans. Schwartz, World of Thought, 29. 114 Pines, Envisioning Eternal Empire, 63. 115 Mencius, trans. Lau, 188. Yi was assumed to be a virtuous minister who could possibly challenge the claims of Ch\u00E2\u0080\u0099i to the throne. 59 his favour, all the while still ensuring that his public image would not be tarnished. Similarly, the virtuous son of Yu who inherited the throne from his father and thus continued the illustrious Xia \u00E5\u00A4\u008F dynasty turns out to be a cold-blooded political murderer. Neither of these accounts is particularly flattering, and it makes me wonder whether or not these figures were being maligned deliberately because of authors\u00E2\u0080\u0099 disagreement with the nonhereditary ideals that they represented. A similar sentiment is expressed in the following passage from the Hanfeizi, which reflects the cynical pragmatism through which the author often explicates his critiques: The so-called sage-rulers and enlightened kings of antiquity succeeded their predecessors not as juniors succeeding seniors in the natural order, but because they had formed parties and gathered influential clans and then molested their superiors, murdered the rulers, and thereby sought after advantage\u00E2\u0080\u00A6Shun intimidated Yao, Y\u00C3\u00BC intimidated Shun, [Tang] banished [Jie], and King Wu censured [Zhou \u00E7\u00B4\u0082]. These four rulers were ministers who murdered their rulers, but All-under-Heaven have extolled them. 116 First of all, this passage starts off immediately by accusing the \u00E2\u0080\u009Cso-called sage-rulers\u00E2\u0080\u009D of being usurpers of a throne that they were not entitled to, as they lacked the hereditary legitimacy that would have been necessary. Worse yet, it is claimed that these usurpers were merely after profits. It is made abundantly clear that the author finds the sage-kings abhorrent, not only because these usurpers were capable of intimidation and murder, but also because their misdeeds have been extolled instead of condemned. Within the particular ruler-centric context of the Hanfeizi, the author\u00E2\u0080\u0099s concerns 116 The Complete Works of Han Fei Tz\u00C7\u0094: a classic of Chinese Political Science, Volume II, \u00E2\u0080\u009CShuoyi\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E8\u00AA\u00AA\u00E7\u0096\u0091 Chapter, trans. W.K. Liao (London, UK: A. Probsthain, 1959). \u00E5\u008F\u00A4\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u0089\u0080\u00E8\u00AC\u0082\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E9\u0095\u00B7\u00E5\u00B9\u00BC\u00E5\u00BC\u00B1\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E5\u008F\u008A\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5 \u00E6\u00AC\u00A1\u00E5\u00BA\u008F\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E6\u0090\u0086\u00E9\u00BB\u00A8\u00E8\u0088\u0087\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0081\u009A\u00E5\u00B7\u00B7\u00E6\u0097\u008F\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E5\u0081\u00AA\u00E4\u00B8\u008A\u00E5\u00BC\u0092\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E6\u00B1\u0082\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u0088\u00A9\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E2\u0080\u00A6\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00E5\u0081\u00AA\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E7\u00A6\u00B9\u00E5\u0081\u00AA\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B9\u00AF\u00E6\u0094\u00BE\u00E6\u00A1\u0080\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E4\u00BC\u0090\u00E7\u00B4\u0082\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00AD\u00A4\u00E5\u009B\u009B \u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E5\u00BC\u0092\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E8\u00AD\u00BD\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E3\u0080\u0082 60 would definitely make sense. Furthermore, the Hanfeizi proceeds to critique how modeling oneself after the sage-kings is actually contributing to the continuation of the chaos: [All-under-Heaven] approves the Tao of Yao and Shun and conforms to it, [this is the reason] there are murderers of rulers and rebels against fathers. Yao, Shun, [Tang], and Wu, each in his turn, acted contrary to the right relationship of ruler and minister, and the moral of the subsequent generations has consequently been upset. Yao, while ruler of men, made a minister his ruler. Shun, while ministering to a ruler, made the ruler a minister. [Tang] and Wu, while ministering to rulers, murdered the sovereigns and dismembered their bodies. Yet All-under Heaven have honoured them. This is the reason why All-under-Heaven has hitherto not attained political order. Indeed, the so-called intelligent ruler is one who is able to keep his ministers in his service; the so-called worthy minister is one who is able to make laws and crimes clear and to attend to his official duties so as to support his master. Now, Yao, assuming himself to be enlightened, could not keep Shun in his service; Shun, assuming himself to be worthy, could not continue supporting Yao; and [Tang] and Wu, assuming themselves to be righteous, murdered their masters and superiors. That was the way \"enlightened\" rulers would give and \"worthy\" ministers would take. In consequence, hitherto there have been sons robbing their fathers' houses and ministers robbing their masters' states. Thus, fathers give way to sons and rulers give way to ministers. 117 From the onset, the Hanfeizi points out both the fact that the succession narratives of Yao and Shun were not only widely known and praised, but because of these misleading tales abhorrent acts of regicidal and patricidal violence came to be encouraged. Similarly, the fact that these narratives demonstrated that challenging and supplanting one\u00E2\u0080\u0099s ruler can be justified at all, is also the reason why much disorder has plagued the later generations, and especially during the Warring States period. Both of these claims of the Hanfeizi 117 Complete Works of Han Fei Tz\u00C7\u0094 \u00E2\u0080\u009CZhong xiao\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E5\u00BF\u00A0\u00E5\u00AD\u009D Chapter, trans. Liao. [\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B]\u00E7\u009A\u0086\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E9\u0081\u0093\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E6\u0098\u00AF \u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E6\u00B3\u0095\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u0098\u00AF\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E5\u00BC\u0092\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E6\u009B\u00B2\u00E6\u0096\u00BC\u00E7\u0088\u00B6\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E6\u00B9\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u0088\u0096\u00E5\u008F\u008D\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E7\u00BE\u00A9\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E4\u00BA\u0082\u00E5\u00BE\u008C\u00E4\u00B8\u0096\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E6\u0095\u0099\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0080\u008C \u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B9\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00BC\u0092\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E4\u00B8\u00BB\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E5\u0088\u0091\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u00B0\u00B8\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E8\u00AD\u00BD\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00AD\u00A4\u00E5\u00A4\u00A9\u00E4\u00B8\u008B\u00E6\u0089\u0080\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E8\u0087\u00B3\u00E4\u00BB\u008A\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E6\u00B2\u00BB \u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E5\u00A4\u00AB\u00E6\u0089\u0080\u00E8\u00AC\u0082\u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0083\u00BD\u00E7\u0095\u009C\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00EF\u00BC\u009B\u00E6\u0089\u0080\u00E8\u00AC\u0082\u00E8\u00B3\u00A2\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0083\u00BD\u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E6\u00B3\u0095\u00E8\u00BE\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E6\u00B2\u00BB\u00E5\u00AE\u0098\u00E8\u0081\u00B7\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E6\u0088\u00B4\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E4\u00BB\u008A\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00E8\u0087\u00AA\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u0082\u00BA \u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E8\u0083\u00BD\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u0095\u009C\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0088\u009C\u00E8\u0087\u00AA\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E8\u00B3\u00A2\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E4\u00B8\u008D\u00E8\u0083\u00BD\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E6\u0088\u00B4\u00E5\u00A0\u00AF\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00B9\u00AF\u00E3\u0080\u0081\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E8\u0087\u00AA\u00E4\u00BB\u00A5\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E7\u00BE\u00A9\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E5\u00BC\u0092\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E9\u0095\u00B7\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E6\u00AD\u00A4\u00E6\u0098\u008E\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E4\u00B8\u0094\u00E5\u00B8\u00B8\u00E8\u0088\u0087\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E8\u0080\u008C\u00E8\u00B3\u00A2\u00E8\u0087\u00A3 \u00E4\u00B8\u0094\u00E5\u00B8\u00B8\u00E5\u008F\u0096\u00E4\u00B9\u009F\u00E3\u0080\u0082\u00E6\u0095\u0085\u00E8\u0087\u00B3\u00E4\u00BB\u008A\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E5\u008F\u0096\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E7\u0088\u00B6\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E5\u00AE\u00B6\u00EF\u00BC\u008C\u00E7\u0082\u00BA\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E8\u0087\u00A3\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E6\u009C\u0089\u00E5\u008F\u0096\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E5\u0090\u009B\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E8\u0080\u0085\u00E7\u009F\u00A3\u00E3\u0080\u0082 61 demonstrate its heavily ruler-centric political ideals, and also attempt to deprive moral justification and legitimacy of any subversive minister and subject. Furthermore, it could also be interpreted as a critique of Warring States political realities. Ideally, rulers ought to be able to keep their ministers in control, and the ideal ministers ought to do all that they were prescribed to do in order to honor their rulers. It could be argued that in this particular use of the Yao and Shun narrative, the Hanfeizi is also criticizing the fact that, during the Warring States, these transgressions between ruler-minister and father-son, were occurring with increasing frequency due to the prevalence of these myths. Both of these sage-king narratives, first of the flood and also of the succession, demonstrate the fact that, by and large, Warring States authors not only had different interpretations sometimes of the same tales, but even more significantly, that it is often possible to observe when they manipulate these narratives in order to present their own particular ideals or react to the explications of others. In particular, just as some texts would readily use the sage-king figures to extol their virtues, there are others that will formulate counter-narratives using the same figures and concepts. 62 4. Conclusion In this project, I have demonstrated that sage-king figures are crucial components in the formulation of Warring States narratives about political ideals and are indispensable as a means to understand the narratives\u00E2\u0080\u0099 conceptualizations of the world. Similarly, far from being mere mythological and historical accounts about an imagined past, these narratives constructed around the sage-kings often underwent evolutionary changes, as different authors interacted and reacted with the ideas that they would come to represent. I surveyed a number of primary and secondary sources in order to present a more comprehensive picture, both in contemporary scholarship as well as in the Warring States texts. In the process of my research, I managed to corroborate the theories and practices of many current leading scholars, such as Puett and Lewis, in the field of early Chinese intellectual history. As a whole, my project was meant to serve as a preliminary survey of contemporary scholarship, especially with respect to how to treat this age-old idea, the sage-kings, as a way to understand or reconstruct the original historical contexts from which these fascinating accounts about the past were formulated. I was able to challenge the notion that sage-king figures in early Chinese thought were concrete and essentialized representations of philosophical ideals and political legitimacy, and instead demonstrated that they were in fact constantly undergoing changes at the hands of the Warring States authors. In particular, what I found to be significant is the fact that the same sage-kings were harshly criticised by some authors, and despite their centrality within the larger discourse, not everyone subscribed to what they represented as manifestations of ideal 63 rulers from the past. Overall, I believe the strength of this project was my historiographically inclined interdisciplinary approach and the breadth of materials that were surveyed. Through a more historically conscious research process, as inspired by Puett, I attempted to conceptualize and present my findings within the original contexts from which they would have been first created. There are obvious limitations to this project as well; in many ways, I attempted to cover too much ground, and thus my analysis of the materials was not as in-depth and profound as what I would have liked. Similarly, most of the translations that I used were drawn from different scholars, and thus it is inevitable that there are some inconsistencies with terminology. Similarly, a more thorough and systematic inclusion of even more primary texts and other sage-king narratives would have allowed me to more effectively buttress my claims. It is my goal to use the findings of this project to further expand my survey of early Chinese political and intellectual history, as a basis for my doctoral research. Especially in light of the discovery of historically significant archaeological materials in the past several decades, both in the form of manuscripts and artefacts, I am hoping that these new materials will challenge us to re-evaluate our previous perceptions and understanding of the political, religious, and philosophical realities of the Warring States. Some of the most intriguing discussions among scholars have been how exactly to best interpret and understand the historical significance of all these recent archaeological finds and what kinds of theoretical approaches are most appropriate to integrate these new findings within the current academic discourse. In order to effectively carry out this kind of research, the archaeological context itself is most important, as it not only gives us 64 clues as to these writings\u00E2\u0080\u0099 authenticity as texts, but it also helps us to date and understand the history of textual transmission as well as possibly the texts\u00E2\u0080\u0099 original purposes. All of this work will not be possible without a more clearly conducted survey of current scholarship, and I believe I have been able to do just that. As a whole, the Warring States texts are only as significant as we are able to extrapolate and effectively contextualize what they reveal about early China. Through my research, I have been able to demonstrate that an idea such as the sage-king, integral to the development of early Chinese thought merely to represent the political ideals of the texts, is actually a lot more complicated, and deserving of more than just a superficial recognition. In approaching this analysis with a more nuanced and historically aware approach, I have been able to suggest the necessity of questioning and also challenging some of these long-held notions about the development of early Chinese history, in hopes that scholars will be able to gain a more accurate and meaningful understanding for future research. 65 5. Bibliography Allan, Sarah. The Heir and the Sage. San Francisco, CA: Chinese Materials Center, 1981. \u00E2\u0080\u0094. The Way of Water and the Sprouts of Virtue. Albany, NY: State University of New York, 1997. Ames, Roger T. The Art of Rulership: A Study of Ancient Chinese Political Thought. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1994. Brisch, Nicole Maria, ed. Divine Kingship in the Ancient World and Beyond. Chicago, IL: Oriental Institute of the University of Chicago, 2008. Bodde, Derk. \"Myths of Ancient China.\" In Essays on Chinese Civilization, edited by Charles Le Blanc and Dorothey Borei. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981. Chang, K. C. Art, Myth, and Ritual: The Path to Political Authority in Ancient China. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983. Ching, Julia. Mysticism and Kingship in China: The Heart of Chinese Wisdom. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1997. Confucius Analects with Selections from Traditional Commentaries. Translated by Edward Slingerland. Indianopolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 2003. 66 Csikszentmihalyi, Mark, and Michael Nylan. \"Constructing Lineages and Inventing Traditions through Exemplary Figures in Early China.\" T'oung Pao 89, no. 3 (2003): 59-99. Deng Guoguang (Tang Gwok Kwong), \u00E9\u0084\u00A7\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E5\u0085\u0089. Sheng wang zhi dao: xian Qin zhu zi de jing shi zhi hui \u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E4\u00B9\u008B\u00E9\u0081\u0093 \u00E5\u0085\u0088\u00E7\u00A7\u00A6\u00E8\u00AB\u00B8\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E7\u009A\u0084\u00E7\u00B6\u0093\u00E4\u00B8\u0096\u00E6\u0099\u00BA\u00E6\u0085\u00A7. Beijing, China: Zhong hua shu ju \u00E4\u00B8\u00AD\u00E8\u008F\u00AF\u00E6\u009B\u00B8\u00E5\u00B1\u0080, 2010. Graham, A. C. Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China. Chicago and La Salle, IL: Open Court Publishing, 1989. Han Feizi: Basic Writings. Translated by Burton Watson. New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 2003. Hanfeizi Jijie \u00E9\u009F\u0093\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E9\u009B\u0086\u00E8\u00A7\u00A3. Edited by Wang Xianshen\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E5\u0085\u0088\u00E6\u0085\u008E. Beijing, China: Zhonghua shuju, 1998. Hsiao, Kung-chuan. A History of Chinese Political Thought: Volume 1: From the Beginnings to the Sixth Century A.D., Translated by F. W. Mote. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979. Ivanhoe, Philip J., trans. The Daodejing of Laozi. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing, 2002. Keightley, David N. \"The Religious Commitment: Shang Theology and the Genesis of Chinese Political Culture.\" History of Religion 17 (1978): 211-224. 67 Keightley, David N., ed. The Origins of Chinese Civilization. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1983. Lewis, Mark Edward. Sanctioned Violence in Early China. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1990. \u00E2\u0080\u0094. The Flood Myths of Early China. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2006. \u00E2\u0080\u0094. Writing and Authority in Early China. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1999. Loewe, Michael, and Edward L. Shaughnessy. The Cambridge History of Ancient China: From the Origins of Civilization to 221 B.C. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Loewe, Michael, ed. Early Chinese Texts: A Bibliographical Guide. Berkeley, CA: The Society for the Study of Early China and The Institute of East Asian Studies, 1993. MacCormack, Geoffrey. \"Mythology and the Origin of Law in Early Chinese Thought.\" Journal of Asian Legal History 1 (2011): 1-22. Mencius. Translated by D. C. Lau. London, UK: Penguin Publishing, 2004. Nylan, Michael, and Michael Loewe, . China's Early Empires: A Re-appraisal. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2010. 68 Pines, Yuri. \u00E2\u0080\u009C\u00E2\u0080\u0098The One That Pervades the All\u00E2\u0080\u0099 in Ancient Chinese Political thought: The Origins of \u00E2\u0080\u0098The Great Unity\u00E2\u0080\u0099 Paradigm.\u00E2\u0080\u009D T\u00E2\u0080\u0099oung Pao, Second Series 86 (2003): 280-324. Pines, Yuri. Envisioning Eternal Empire: Chinese Political Thought of the Warring States Era. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawai'i Press, 2009. Puett, Michael. \"Human and Divine Kingship in Early China: Comparative Reflections.\" In Religion and Power: Divine Kingship in the Ancient World and Beyond, edited by Nicole Brisch. Chicago, IL: Oriental Institute, University of Chicago, 2008. \u00E2\u0080\u0094.\"Sages, Ministers, and Rebels: Narratives from Early China Concerning the Initial Creation of the State.\" Harvard Journal of Asiatic Studies 58, no. 2 (December 1998): 425-479. \u00E2\u0080\u0094. The Ambivalence of Creation: Debates Concerning Innovation and Artifice in Early China. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2001. \u00E2\u0080\u0094. To Become a God: Cosmology, Sacrifice, and Self-Divinization in Early China. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Asia Center, 2002. Schwartz, Bejamin. The World of Thought in Ancient China.Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of the Harvard University Press, 1985. Slingerland, Edward. Effortless Action: Wu-wei as Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 2003. 69 The Complete Works of Han Fei Tz\u00C7\u0094: a classic of Chinese Political Science, Volume II. Translated by W.K. Liao. London, UK: A. Probsthain, 1959. Von Falkenhausen, Lothar. Chinese Society in the Age of Confucius (1000\u00E2\u0080\u0093250 BC): The Archaeological Evidence. Los Angeles, CA: Cotsen Institute of Archaeology, UCLA, 2006. Wang, Hsiao-Po and Leo S. Chang. The Philosophical Foundations of Han Fei\u00E2\u0080\u0099s Political Theory. Honolulu, HI: University of Hawaii Press, 1986. Wang Jianwen \u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E5\u0081\u00A5\u00E6\u0096\u0087. Zhanguo zhuzi de gushengwang chuangshuo ji qi sixiangshi yiyi \u00E6\u0088\u00B0\u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E8\u00AB\u00B8\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E7\u009A\u0084\u00E5\u008F\u00A4\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E5\u0082\u00B3\u00E8\u00AA\u00AA\u00E5\u008F\u008A\u00E5\u0085\u00B6\u00E6\u0080\u009D\u00E6\u0083\u00B3\u00E5\u008F\u00B2\u00E6\u0084\u008F\u00E7\u00BE\u00A9. Taipei, Taiwan: Guo li Taiwan da xue chu ban wei yuan hui \u00E5\u009C\u008B\u00E7\u00AB\u008B\u00E8\u0087\u00BA\u00E7\u0081\u00A3\u00E5\u00A4\u00A7\u00E5\u00AD\u00B8\u00E5\u0087\u00BA\u00E7\u0089\u0088\u00E5\u00A7\u0094\u00E5\u0093\u00A1\u00E6\u009C\u0083, 1987. Xinshi Hanfeizi \u00E6\u0096\u00B0\u00E9\u0087\u008B\u00E9\u009F\u0093\u00E9\u009D\u009E\u00E5\u00AD\u0090. Edited by Lai Yanyuan \u00E8\u00B3\u00B4\u00E7\u0082\u008E\u00E5\u0085\u0083 and Fu Wuguang \u00E5\u0082\u0085\u00E6\u00AD\u00A6\u00E5\u0085\u0089, Taipei, Taiwan: Sanmin shuju, 2007. Yoshinaga Shinjiro \u00E5\u0090\u0089\u00E6\u00B0\u00B8\u00E6\u0085\u008E\u00E4\u00BA\u008C\u00E9\u0083\u008E. \u00E2\u0080\u009CM\u00C5\u008Dshi ni okeru S\u00C4\u0093\u00C5\u008D to Seinin: Sono Bokka shis\u00C5\u008D no juy\u00C5\u008D\u00E2\u0080\u009D \u00E5\u00AD\u009F\u00E5\u00AD\u0090\u00E3\u0081\u00AB\u00E3\u0081\u008A\u00E3\u0081\u0091\u00E3\u0082\u008B\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E7\u008E\u008B\u00E3\u0081\u00A8\u00E8\u0081\u0096\u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E3\u0081\u009D\u00E3\u0081\u00AE\u00E5\u00A2\u00A8\u00E5\u00AE\u00B6\u00E6\u0080\u009D\u00E6\u0083\u00B3\u00E3\u0081\u00AE\u00E5\u008F\u0097\u00E5\u00AE\u00B9.Akita Daigaku ky\u00C5\u008Diku gakubu kenky\u00C5\u00AB kiy\u00C5\u008D\u00EF\u00BC\u009Ajinbun kagaku shakai kagaku \u00E7\u00A7\u008B\u00E7\u0094\u00B0\u00E5\u00A4\u00A7\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6\u00E6\u0095\u0099\u00E8\u0082\u00B2\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6\u00E9\u0083\u00A8\u00E7\u00A0\u0094\u00E7\u00A9\u00B6\u00E7\u00B4\u0080\u00E8\u00A6\u0081 \u00E4\u00BA\u00BA\u00E6\u0096\u0087\u00E7\u00A7\u0091\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6\u00E3\u0083\u00BB\u00E7\u00A4\u00BE\u00E4\u00BC\u009A\u00E7\u00A7\u0091\u00E5\u00AD\u00A6 48 (1995): 49-63. Zhuangzi : The Essential Writings with Selections from Traditional Commentaries. Translated by Brook Ziporyn. Indianopolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. "@en . "Thesis/Dissertation"@en . "2013-05"@en . "10.14288/1.0073403"@en . "eng"@en . "Asian Studies"@en . "Vancouver : University of British Columbia Library"@en . "University of British Columbia"@en . "Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 3.0 Unported"@en . "http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/"@en . "Graduate"@en . "Development of the Sage-King narratives : idealized concepts of rulership in Warring States Chinese thought"@en . "Text"@en . "http://hdl.handle.net/2429/43654"@en .