UBC Theses and Dissertations

UBC Theses Logo

UBC Theses and Dissertations

Diderot, art, and the eighteenth-century ethos De Rosier, Charlotte Milam 1971

You don't seem to have a PDF reader installed, try download the pdf

Item Metadata

Download

Media
[if-you-see-this-DO-NOT-CLICK]
UBC_1971_A8 D47.pdf [ 7.9MB ]
Metadata
JSON: 1.0102179.json
JSON-LD: 1.0102179+ld.json
RDF/XML (Pretty): 1.0102179.xml
RDF/JSON: 1.0102179+rdf.json
Turtle: 1.0102179+rdf-turtle.txt
N-Triples: 1.0102179+rdf-ntriples.txt
Original Record: 1.0102179 +original-record.json
Full Text
1.0102179.txt
Citation
1.0102179.ris

Full Text

DIDEROT, ART, AND THE EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY ETHOS by CHARLOTTE MILAM DE ROSIER B.A.. University of Washington, I967  A THESIS SUBMITTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS  i n the Department of  FRENCH We accept this thesis as conforming to the required standard  THE UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA September, 1971  In p r e s e n t i n g an  this  thesis  advanced degree at  the  Library  I further for  shall  the  agree that  his  permission  of  this  written  representatives.  for extensive  g r a n t e d by  1971  the  It i s understood gain  TTRETOfiff  fiftpt.pmhftr,  British  available for  permission.  The U n i v e r s i t y o f B r i t i s h V a n c o u v e r 8, Canada /  Date  be  thes.is f o r f i n a n c i a l  Department of  f u l f i l m e n t of  U n i v e r s i t y of  make i t f r e e l y  s c h o l a r l y p u r p o s e s may  by  in p a r t i a l  Columbia  shall  requirements  Columbia,  Head o f my  be  I agree  r e f e r e n c e and copying of  that  not  the  that  Study.  this  thesis  Department  copying or  for  or  publication  allowed without  my  This study explores the interdependent  r e l a t i o n s h i p between  Diderot's writings on art, the art of eighteenth-century and the times that produced them both.  France,  Accordingly, the study  f a l l s i n t o three p r i n c i p a l r e l a t e d sections, with each enlarging upon a s p e c i f i c facet of the t o p i c .  Proceeding from the premise  that both Diderot and the paintings he discussed belonged within a p a r t i c u l a r c u l t u r a l context of tastes, ideas, and h i s t o r i c a l facts, the f i r s t p r i n c i p a l d i v i s i o n , "Diderot i n the Scheme of Things", begins as a b r i e f survey of the a r t i s t i c r e a l i t i e s that prevailed i n France p r i o r to the approximate period spanned by the Salons i n order to present a general view of the e c l e c t i c body of a r t on which he based the substance  of h i s commentaries.  The r e l a t e d section on "Diderot's Aesthetics" s p e c i f i e s a c e r t a i n problem i n discussing Diderot's w r i t i n g on art and demonstrates that Diderot's a r t i s t i c notions cannot be treated from a general aesthetic standpoint but can be understood of the i n d i v i d u a l c r i t i c i s m s themselves.  only i n terms  The "Essay on Painting"  presents a compendium of the themes and ideas that Diderot applied i n those i n d i v i d u a l c r i t i c i s m s .  Both the section e n t i t l e d  rot's Aesthetics" and the one dealing with the "Essay"  "Dide-  present  t r a n s i t i o n a l introductory material f o r the second major d i v i s i o n , "The Salons:  1759-1781", which deals with i n d i v i d u a l c r i t i c i s m s  of s p e c i f i c paintings to show Diderot's c r i t i c a l method at work  i n a varied range of representative works and to show i n what way Diderot f a i l s to understand the paintings before him i n the idiom of the a r t i s t . On the basis of this conclusion, i t would be easy to dismiss much of his commentary on the ground that i t i s quaint but inadequate; the f i n a l major division builds on this possible conclusion, however, to explore a further facet of the Salons and shows, through i t s focus on the Salon of I767 that Diderot's commentaries were not merely criticisms of art but of society as well and that his a t t i tude toward the needs and faults of society conditioned his approach to art. In i t s substance, this section offers the view that because of—rather than i n spite o f — i t s polarities and inconsistencies, Diderot's thoughts on contemporary art provide a faithful reflection i n small of identical conflicts and aspirations i n the larger context of eighteenth-century French society.  Diderot's values and  the values of his time emerge from his application of those values to contemporary art. With art as the matrix, the values of the man. and those of the society present themselves at the conclusion of the study as a mosaic of concepts i n opposition—a mosaic where each conceptual element attains i t s meaning i n juxtaposition, rather than i n harmony, with the others.  DIDEROT, ART, AND THE EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY ETHOS CONTENTS Introduction  page one  Diderot in the Scheme of Things  5  Diderot's "Aesthetics" as Key to His Criticism  16  The Essay on Painting:  Synopsis  19  The Essay on Painting:  I765  20  The Salons:  I759-I78I  Diderot's Taste and Method Diderot as Critic  38 '  69  Diderot's Values and the Eighteenth-Century Ethos  75  The Salon of 1767  79  Progress and Reversion  83  Reason and Intuition  86  Morality and Antimorality  88  Disguise and Discovery  93  The Spiritual and the Temporal  97  Melancholy and the Pursuit of Happiness  99  Sources Consulted  109  Works Cited  112  Footnotes  11^  Illustrations  123  INTRODUCTION  A l i t e r a t u r e professor once advised his class that i f they wanted to discover the s p i r i t of an age or period, i t s code of v a l u e s — s o c i a l , moral, and a r t i s t i c — t h e y would not f i n d those c h a r a c t e r i s t i c s to be obvious i n the best works of the time, but i n the worst.  The best works of art possess a q u a l i t y that ab-  s t r a c t s them from time and place, that preserves them from becoming obsolete or commonplace; the worst o f f e r i n g s , on the other hand, tend to be transparent:  the " s t r i n g s " show, and we are more  aware of what the a r t i s t i s t r y i n g to do than we are of what he has done.  Subtlety i s gone.  In the best, form i s a vehicle f o r  content; i n the worst, form i s content.  In eighteenth-century  France, t h i s p r i n c i p l e of looking to the best f o r content and to the worst f o r form i s borne out i n a comparison of the works of Chardin and Greuze, but i t i s Diderot's judgment of them, more than the works themselves, which gives us the greatest insight into the values of the time. Germain Bazin has written that at i t s highest l e v e l s , the painting of a country i s also a p o r t r a i t of i t s s p i r i t and soul.^ But experience shows that the greatest among works of art address themselves to s p i r i t u a l or humanistic ideals rather than to nationalistic  ones; they speak to the man,  not to the c i t i z e n , and  might—more a c c u r a t e l y — c o n s t i t u t e a p o r t r a i t of the s p i r i t  and  soul of man.  Thus, the best art of a country may» i n f a c t ,  us very l i t t l e about the s p i r i t of that country:  tell  Rembrandt's  p o r t r a i t s , f o r example, reveal very l i t t l e about Amsterdam and i t s values and tastes:  the fact that he died alone i n abject  poverty reveals much more. When art i s being made to order, however, i t does serve as a d i r e c t and v a l i d r e f l e c t i o n of the values of the time, and i n eighteenth-century France, the existence of the Academy of Painting and Sculpture provides us with a case i n point.  In the early  eighteenth-century, as i n the time of Louis XIV, the output of the Academy d i d not extend to a l l l e v e l s of society; to the extent that s p e c i f i c paintings were ordered by and executed f o r s p e c i f i c patrons, painting r e f l e c t e d taste, but i t was the t a s t e of an e l i t e and not of  society at large.  exhibitions i n 1737,  With the appearance of the b i e n n i a l Salon art became a public a f f a i r , no longer merely  a c r a f t i n the service of the king; i t was o f f e r e d f o r praise, f o r c r i t i c i s m , and f o r sale. public to please.  For painters without patrons there was  The eighteenth century was  t i n u i t y and by change:  a  characterized by con-  To what extent, then, d i d painting as a  whole r e f l e c t the thought of the society i n which i t was produced'' Jean Starobinski has observed i n t h i s regard that i n order to capture the " l i v i n g r e a l i t y " of the eighteenth century, one cannot consider either the art or the thought of the time i n i s o l a t i o n , that the two are i n d i v i s i b l e , having a common h i s t o r i c a l and s o c i a l origin.  Later i n the same study, he appears to combat t h i s con-  clusion by warning that i t has often been i n s u f f i c i e n t l y stressed that a r t , "at any h i s t o r i c a l period whatsoever, i s not a d i r e c t  expression of the u n i v e r s a l state of a given society: marily the prerogative of the wealthy who  i t i s pri-  order and appreciate works  of art according to the c r i t e r i a of t h e i r own taste and culture."3 The problem, i n r e s o l v i n g the apparent contradiction, i s neither to prove nor to disprove e i t h e r statement, but rather to consider them as equal and opposite truths.  The paradox existing, therefore,  that art r e f l e c t s the thought of the time, and that art i s p r i m a r i l y the prerogative of the wealthy and r e f l e c t s the taste of a p a r t i c u l a r s o c i a l class, how  can one set out to demonstrate with v a l i d i t y that  the s o c i a l and aesthetic thought of a period i s embodied i n i t s painting?  Would one look to the best of the paintings or to the  worst of them to i l l u s t r a t e the s p i r i t of the age? perhaps embody the enduring ideals of man,  The best would  while the worst would  present the popular forms; neither would be wholly representative. Would one be able to detect exaggerations  or omissions of the  thought that i t i s supposed to r e f l e c t and thereby gauge to what extent art also f a i l s as a r e l i a b l e index to contemporary thought? As t h i s question applies to eighteenth-century France, perhaps the complex i n t e r r e l a t i o n s h i p between art and thought can best be understood with the help of a contemporary, one who  was neither a r t i s t ,  nor a r i s t o c r a t , nor merely c i t i z e n , yet very much i n tune with the ideas of the time, someone who was both participant and  observer.  Although Diderot d i d not set out i n his Salon commentaries to approximate art and society, his writings on art provide us with a more representative accounting than any purely h i s t o r i c a l or antiquarian c o r r e l a t i o n of the two, because he judges according to contemporary values, and t e l l s us—through his praise and blame—  to what extent those values are present, wanting, or d i s t o r t e d i n the paintings he discusses.  Time has not n e c e s s a r i l y corroborated  his judgments as to what was best and what was worst i n the painting of h i s time, but as he stood before the best and the worst of i t , attempting both to understand i t and to i n s p i r e i t , he established a concentricity of a r t and Enlightenment  thought, not by a scholarly  superimposition of the two, but by bringing the v i c i s s i t u d e s of Enlightenment thought to bear on the art of h i s time and by judging i t accordingly.  This study w i l l examine Diderot s writings on 1  painting i n order to i d e n t i f y the values underlying h i s judgments and t o i n d i c a t e to what extent h i s values coincide with the s o c i a l and aesthetic values of h i s time.  DIDEROT IN THE SCHEME OF THINGS  The twentieth-century observer who looks at a painting which once hung i n the Salon of the Academy of France might not only see different elements i n that painting than Diderot saw, but might also expect—because of his historical and cultural perspective— far different qualities than Diderot, i n his time, expected.  Art  i t s e l f may be as old as mankind, but man's conception of what i t i s and what i t ought to do changes with the generations; and just as the criteria of taste vary with the passage of time, so the ways of looking at a painting vary as well.  Both Diderot and the paint-  ings he discussed were situated i n and conditioned by a specific cultural context of social conditions, prevailing tastes, and philosophical ideas; any discussion of the views that Diderot brought to bear on the paintings he discussed, therefore, would perhaps assume more meaning within the context of a familiarity with the a r t i s t i c realities of the period. Art exhibitions i n eighteenth-century France contributed significantly to the development of modern criticism i n that they provided opportunities for c r i t i c a l reports, representing a new form of art criticism, uniquely adapted to the purpose which i t was  intended  to serve, where the procedure no longer consisted of inserting judgments between the facts referred to and the "rules of art"—as had been the case with ancient and medieval treatises and Renaissance "Lives" of artists«but of writing extraneously and with relative informality to give a personal opinion upon a group of works and artists.  The f i r s t of these c r i t i c a l reports was an essay by La Font de Saint-Yenne^, entitled Reflexions sur quelques causes de l'etat present de l a peinture en France , which appeared i n 17^7  and  ex-  pressed the author's lament that the genre of historical painting had fallen into neglect during the decade since the Salon exhibitions of painting and sculpture began i n 1.731- Saint-Yenne' s attachment to historical painting was born of a belief that i t was the highest form of painting because i t was the only vehicle capable of transmitting noble ideas to posterity.3  He attacked the frivolous  taste of his day, catered to and i n a sense sustained by those artists who  seemed to prefer prostitution of their art to outright starvation  as martyrs to Saint-Yenne's favorite cause.  Had i t not been for the  popularity of rococo art and a l l i t s attendant evils of patronage, superficiality and eroticism, historical painting would not hsve had to suffer the abuse of neglect or indifference that now  existed;  His attack against the fashionable rococo was also an appeal to the artists to restore honor and dignity to their art by portraying h.  noble themes capable of instructing the mind and inspiring the soul. The essay x^as badly received by artists who had grown acutely sensitive to criticism during long years of underexposure to the public gaze, when practitioners of fine arts and crafts labored at the court i n the sheltered workshop of the King.  Saint-Yenne, for his part,  nursed traditional academic tendencies and was possessed of a constitutional incapacity for the appreciation of contemporary art. It remained for Diderot to add the touch of authority when, twelve years later, he began the writing of the f i r s t of his biennial Salon commentaries.  Not only were his literary credentials more impressive  than Saint-Yenne's to begin with, but his prejudices were more i n -  teresting as well.  Unlike Saint-Yenne s, Diderot's opinions were 1  not intended for publication in his own country, but for private circulation i n Friedrich Grimm's Correspondance l i t t 6 r a i r e , whose subscribers included francophile princes throughout Europe.  Diderot  was a man of letters writing for other men of letters, so that his theoretical and practical preparation for discussing and evaluating art, though limited, was not of paramount importance to his reading audience. Although Diderot's approach to painting was not so exclusively puritanical as was Saint-Yenne's, a tension does exist i n his own commentaries between the merits of traditional art and the vogue of the moment. This tension reflects i n general the a r t i s t i c state of affairs i n France, the co-existence of classical and rococo art, each genre produced by and depicting a unique system of values. Although the two genres and value systems were, from almost every standpoint, at odds with each other, Diderot's values and tastes as an art c r i t i c derived from both of them. More than a hundred years before Diderot began his novitiate as an art c r i t i c , Louis XIV had established Versailles as the nucleus of French culture, the pivot point of an authoritarian regime, and a place for the solemn celebration of the religion of monarchy.  Statues,  galleries, marble halls, and mirrors framed the attendant ceremonials. Where wealth concentrates i n the hands of a few and where lack of i n dustrial development precludes investment elsewhere, the only other outlet—human nature being what i t i s — i n v a r i a b l y becomes the adornment of abode and person.  In keeping with both the insatiable taste  for finer things and with the aura of formality that pervaded the place, Louis founded, i n 1 6 4 8 , the Royal Academy of Painting and  Sculpture.  Deriving as i t did from an edict of the King, the Aca-  demy possessed and exercised more authority than a mere professional organization could have exercised. and sponsorship,  With this o f f i c i a l recognition  painting had, i n one sense, come a long way:  Through  a l l the ages of Greece and Rome, golden and otherwise, painters were considered xjith the contempt deemed befitting manual laborers, and they were somewhat less despised than actors and cut-purses on a rapidly-descending hierarchical scale.  For succeeding centuries,  painting had been a trade under the guild system, and now—to judge from the stated purpose at the founding of the Academy—the art of painting was once again to be favored, this time with an organization to define and maintain professional standards.  Not stated was  the  fact that this centralization was part of a uniform control of a l l creative activity, whose function from that time forward would be to further the glorification of France i n the person of the King. What Diderot referred to i n his commentaries as "academic art" had i t s beginnings here.  Lectures and discussions at the Academy  were held for the purpose of formulating generally valid and comprehensive rules as part of a program of keeping artists i n the paths of strict a r t i s t i c respectability.  The doctrines of the Academy  were inflexible with regard to acceptable style and subject matter. The art of classic Antiquity was held to be perfect and was the model to be imitated; Nature, i f observed at a l l , was to be compared with classic forms and corrected accordingly; only noble subjects, drawn from poetry or ancient history, were to be depicted, and for expressive and structural purposes, drawing ranked above color. Thus the academicians idealized Nature by imposing an idea of beauty upon i t , specifically, the beauty of ancient art, actual examples of which, *  moreover, they had never seen.  The doctrine of decorum forbade the  depiction of the violent, the ugly, or the base, because classicism also concerned i t s e l f with the effect of art upon the audience.  This  principle derived by analogy from Horace's writings on the drama, wherein he suggested that the purpose of art i s to combine pleasure with instruction, thereby giving art a moral u t i l i t y through pleasure. Saint-Yenne picked up this same theme when he saw, some years later, that historical painting was falling by the wayside.  While academic  doctrines were themselves inflexible, they were somewhat more d i f f i cult to enforce i n actual practice because the doctrine of the imitation of Nature was—in and of i t s e l f — s o vague that i t was construed to allow almost a l l kinds of representation, from naturalism to abstract idealism and everything i n between. The importance of academic art i n any discussion of the artistic climate of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century France is that i t subsumed the principles of classicism, the f i r s t of which was imitation and subsequently, impersonality and conformity to rules.  Artists who  painted i n the classical style were then, i n a sense, absent, since no hint was permitted on the canvas of their own ideas, lives, or experiences.  As for conformity to rules, this was a precondition of  successful imitation, since the selected and "recognized" aesthetic qualities of the masterpieces had been codified and systematized as rules.  And finally, the Academy's inductive process of rule-making  echoed the classical belief i n the effective existence of absolute values i n matters pertaining to the creation of art. In art, the formation of an academy i s one sign that the golden age is past; i t indicates that the spirit of the time i s primarily reproductive and antiquarian and only secondarily—or accidentally—  creative.  Diderot was aware, even at the time he was serving as Grimm's  Parisian c r i t i c , that another golden age was past: Quand voit-on nartre les critiques et les grammairiens? Tout juste aprds l e sidcle du genie et des productions divines.3  Even before Louis death, the Grand Manner had begun to pall, and the 1  King's taste i t s e l f had shifted to a preference for more youthfulness and spirit and less seriousness i n art. This shift in taste was to grow and endure as the rococo tradition for many years to come. With the death of the King and the coming of the Regency, the nobles and courtiers abandoned Versailles and descended-upon Paris.  With the  center of cultural l i f e now shifted from the court to the city, the upper classes—newly freed from an intensively ceremonial and r i t u a l i s t i c l i f e — e x e r c i s e d their own taste, avoiding the gravity and austerity of historical painting and f a l l i n g heavily for capricious, pretty, and feminine themes.  Art kept pace with demand, as a certain amount of i t  always does, and to satisfy the new taste of the aristocracy, i t was engaged more heavily than ever i n the service of the fantastic and the erotic.  Each represented, after a l l , a means of escape:  fantasy, the  removal of one's attention from contemporary l i f e , and eroticism, a means to a change of fare.  Literature and theater of the time abounded  i n comparable motifs with impersonations, disguises, mistaken identities, and the siege and surrender of virtue.  The artist Boucher excelled i n  the execution of such themes with his portrayals of buxom shepherdesses and pink-bottomed goddesses.  The settings were fanciful but the glances  and gestures were most r e a l i s t i c . In i t s preoccupation with decorative pleasantry and glorified nudity, or simply with languid prettihess, the rococo style expressed  the special society for which i t was set to work, where mundane values constituted the highest moral code.  Large-scale adornment of aristo-  cratic lodgings created a great demand for paintings which quite naturally were sought after, i n turn, by state o f f i c i a l s , cardinals, social pretenders, visiting nobles, and lesser aristocrats.  With a  clamoring and socially-climbing clientele whose needs and interests did not extend to a r t i s t i c originality, there was more competition among the customers than among the craftsmen.  Mediocrity had estab-  lished i t s dominion over a f l o r i d acreage of canvases, and painting had extended the scope of i t s interests a l l the way from the boudoir to the bonbonnidre.  This, then, was the rococo, certainly l i v e l i e r  and more colorful than anything the Academy had produced theretofore; i t was, after a l l , created to appeal to surfeited aristocratic tastes; i t was lavish and erotic, but i n an impeccable and sophisticated way; awd although i t s content may have been shallow from a thematic point of view, i t was by no means an unworthy successor, i n that respect, to the academic classicism of the golden age. Although Diderot seldom had anything favorable to say about Boucher,'' there was a place i n his heart for rococo subjects with their 7  forthright appeal to the senses, just as there was a place i n his mind for the noble subjects of historical painting whose characters were drawn from history or classical literature, and whose noble themes served a useful, moral purpose i n depicting worthy examples for the masses.  As a study of his Salon commentaries w i l l show, Diderot, as  a c r i t i c stood between both worlds, nourished by both of them, seeing the faults i n each, and yet unable to choose finally between them. Saint-Yenne had no. such difficulty, as we have seen from the substance of his c r i t i c a l writings i n Reflexions,° published i n 1?47.  Those writings, i n fact, represented the beginnings of a reaction against the fashionable rococo—a reaction which was gaining momentum during the middle years of the eighteenth century and which paved the way,  along with the influential writings of the German archaeologist,  Johann Winckelmann, for the new cult of antiquity which culminated i n the neo-classical style of Jacques-Louis David.  The reason that such  writers as Saint-Yenne and Winckelmann could have so much influence in France during their own time and that Diderot's writings on art should have only marginal influence, gaining indirect exposure only through publication of his other works, can be found i n the fact that the Correspondance litteraire —which contained a l l his writings on art—was circulated outside France and was not published u n t i l after his death.  The activities of the three men were related, however,  i n that Saint-Yenne and Winckelmann helped to forge the cross-currents in the art which formed the basis of Diderot's Salon commentaries. Even though his commentaries were innocuous as a contemporary influence, they contributed outside France to the same assault against the rococo that the works of Saint-Yenne and Winckelmann waged from within. The German archaeologist, Winckelmann, rhapsodized at great length about the unique and unattainable perfection of Greek art and because of his zeal and the eager credulity of his reading audience he influenced the tone of art criticism for two centuries to come. He was,  f i r s t of  a l l , an archaeologist, and i t was largely through his efforts, especially his Thoughts on the Imitation of Greek Art in Painting and Sculpture ( 1 7 5 5 ) ^ and his most important work, History of Ancient Art  (1764)^  which contained descriptions of the very recent discoveries (1762-64) at Pompeii and Herculane'um, that the taste for things antique capti-  vated the popular European imagination, and the movement that posterity knows as neo-classicism was born. Admiration for the Ancients had existed long before this, of course, i n literary as well as a r t i s t i c circles, but the discovery of actual examples of ancient art (even though these artifacts proved to be Roman and not Greek), fostered a sense of the immediate presence of antiquity and, what i s more important, this discovery supplemented with actual physical illustrations xirhat the western world had known only indirectly through Greek and Roman writers for mere than eighteen hundred years.  I f classicism was born of, and perpetuated by, a  veneration for the ideals of the antique past, neo-classicism was made possible by the temporarily-subdued  presence of that entrenched classi-  cism i n the f i r s t instance and to the new science of archaeology in the second; and to the architectural, sculptural, literary, and moral ideals preserved by and characteristic of classicism, could now be added—legitimately—the p i c t o r i a l .  And Johann Winckelmann, who never  saw an original piece of Greek painting in his l i f e , furnished an impetus to the flowering of art criticism throughout  eighteenth-cen-  tury Europe and propagated with renewed'solemnity the everlasting prejudice that the only possibility of greatness i n art lay i n imitation of the Ancients. To give some parenthetical insight into both the soundness of Winckelmann s views and the historical facts that conditioned them, 1  i t should be noted that the Pompeiian excavations actually yielded Roman copies of Greek works. No Greek painting had survived into the Christian era, and of Roman painting, the only examples at Pompeii were frescoes that had been buried i n 79 A. D. They included no surpassing a r t — a s paintings—and served the only purpose that,  for example, a painted view from a painted balcony can serve. only "idea" these frescoes expressed—a  The  pre-eminent element of content  that Diderot, too, associated with ancient art—was probably not so much a representation of morality or v i r t u e — a notion cherished by opponents of the rococo—as of milady's wish to extend or multiply her horizons.  Winckelmann, then, knew ancient art almost exclusively  through Roman copies and, of course, Latin literature.  The actual  discovery of authentic Greek art did not properly begin u n t i l 1800 when Lord Elgin plundered the Acropolis to carry sculptures home to London. The neo-classic reaction to the rococo was to find i t s most devoted and accomplished exponent and practitioner toward the end of the century i n Jacques-Louis David, who later became the o f f i c i a l painter of the Revolution, and whose single most genuine contribution to art and humanity was that he saved Fragonard from the guillotine. In the meantime, mid-century was a period when Diderot's c r i t i c a l activities coincided with the confluence of at least four trends in painting:  (l) The timely death of academic classicism had not yet  come: there remained the i r r e s i s t i b l e magnetism of classical antiquity, made a l l the more accessible by the availability, to the right person, of the prestigious Prix de Rome;  (2)  the rococo successor  to classicism, for a l l i t s light-hearted depictions of the carefree rich gamboling and disporting themselves by day and by night or masquerading as country folk, nevertheless preserved of i t s forerunner the very French legacy of the bienseances:  the voilent and the lowly  or common were scrupulously avoided; the rococo, moreover, retained pretensions to classical respectability i n that like the historical and mythological subject matter hawked by the Academy, the subject  matter of much rococo painting derived as well from a source i n antiquity—namely, fable.  (3)  The scientific s p i r i t was i n the air, and  the endless possibilities of scientific investigation for the furtherance of empirical knowledge and, therefore, of progress, gained new and more enthusiastic adherents day by day.  So when Winckelmann's  writings about the recently-unearthed v i l l a s and their art treasures began to circulate i n Europe, the fad for the copying of antique art and ideas spread quickly i n their wake. The old reverence for things classical was now supplemented with the new reverence for science. The respectability and i n f a l l i b i l i t y of such a worthy combination was something that was not to be questioned. * Neo-classicism satisfied the scientific mind—if that mind cared for art at a l l — j u s t as surely as the rococo found an echo of responsive warmth i n the bosom of the aristocracy.  Partly as a reaction to the a r t i f i c i a l i t y and  excesses of the aristocracy, partly as an adjunct to the rise of the bourgeoisie, partly as an inevitable result of the popular cult of Nature, and partly as an adjunct of seventeenth-century Dutch painting, there arose a fourth very popular artistic current: genre painting, or scenes of daily l i f e .  To the Arcadian scenes of the old classi-  cism, the glittering fantasies of the rococo, and the scenes of imagined antiquity now depicted with a new precision and authenticity, was added with a boldness born of confidence-in-numbers—the commonplace.  Just as a particular style of a r t i s t i c expression reflects  not only the artist but the culture that produced i t , so i t was with the Protestant Dutch painters of the seventeenth century who specialized i n portraits, landscapes, and genre scenes i n deference to John Calvin's dictum that man should not paint or carve anything except what he could see about him, so that God's majesty might not be cor-  rupted by fantasies.  A l l this was swept along with a tide of senti-  mentalism from England, so that the genre held great appeal not only for those who were philosophically or emotionally involved with the cult of Nature and the simple l i f e , but for those people as well for whom such pictures reflected their own way of l i f e — e i t h e r sentimentally or with a certain spiritual comprehension—depending upon whether the artist involved was a Greuze or a Chardin.  This, then, was the  eclectic body of art on which Diderot based his judgments, and these were the times that shaped his thoughts.  DIDEROT'S "AESTHETICS" AS KEY TO HIS CRITICISM  The eighteenth century saw the advent not only of art exhibitions but of the discipline of aesthetics as well.  That branch of philo-  sophy which Baumgarten originated'! and dubbed was significant at the time i n asserting the independence and validity of imagination when such a notion was ( o f f i c i a l l y ) unthinkable, i f i t was taken seriously at a l l .  Aesthetics i s properly a branch of philosophy and not of art;  as they pertain to criticism, aesthetic speculations and "truths" are often far too abstract to serve as criteria for the criticism of art anyway; as a "science of the imagination", i t has l i t t l e application to actual works of imagination and represents at best, for c r i t i c a l purposes, a respectable authority to be summoned i n time of need.  Diderot's  aesthetics, then are not of an abstract metaphysical stripe; i n fact, in searching for a word to characterize Diderot's aesthetics—the values or principles with which he approached art—one would have to  conclude that they are elusive: tently applied.  consistently present, but inconsis-  This intellectually-seductive elusive quality has  ensnared some c r i t i c s and tempted them to compile an aesthetics which they might then attribute to Diderot. Nature, goodness, truth, and beauty are proper to any philosopher's conundrum, and Diderot cast them i n the likeness of the Trinity i n Le neveu de Rameau: L empire de l a nature et de ma t r i n i t e . . .le Vrai qui est l e Pe're, et qui engendre l e Bon qui est l e F i l s ; d'oii procede l e beau qui est l e Saint-esprit. (Cited by H. M^lbjerg i n Aspects de 1'esthetique de Diderot) 1  2  The eminently cosmic scope of this concept as well as i t s intrinsic vagueness, as Diderot uses i t , invites i t s citation by some c r i t i c s as the pivot point, the base, and the essence of his aesthetic philosophy.  But since Diderot's references to a l l the different arts  occur throughout his works, and since examples used to support i t are drawn from as wide a sector, this view must hold either that a l l the works circumambient to this " t r i n i t y " are expositions and i l l u s trations of i t or that i t i s the summa of the circumambient works; alas for such interpretations, Diderot's eclectic thought does not lend i t s e l f to such solemn pigeon-holing. The term aesthetics implies more systematization and coherence than Diderot's ideas on art actually have, and their diffuse and often contradictory nature creates a void which quite' naturally has attracted two flourishing c r i t i c a l industries:  exegesis and apologetics.  success of both enterprises depends upon distortion:  The  the exegete  must impose a superficial order according to a preconceived notion of what form that order ought to take and then derive a meaning from his  manipulations; the apologist must defend inconsistency without examining i t s possible merits and without admitting of i t s possible hazards. But any series of observations, maxims, judgments, ripped untimely from their context and planted—for incubation—in the c r i t i c ' s procrustean bed, are doomed to come up smelling of contrivance, since the selected comments unfailingly support the interpretation advanced. More flexible and resilient than his interpreters, Diderot does not insist upon arranging the other aspects of his thought according to the exigencies of a triune vagary from Le neveu de Rameau.  Diderot,  in spite of a l l the efforts of exegetical and apologetic criticism, i s often inconsistent, often vague, and those' who wish to d i s t i l l his ideas on beauty, truth, etc., are forced by the nature of the material to catalogue his uses of these terms in their various contexts, for want of a precise and f i n a l definition.  In like manner, any attempt  to understand the principles by which he judged the contemporary art of the Salons must deal with specific instances; the key to Diderot's art criticism l i e s not i n a pre-conceived and -formulated but i n the individual criticisms themselves.  aesthetics  In the meantime, Dide-  rot's strength i s not so much that he can withstand attack as that he can survive such defenders.  THE ESSAY ON PAINTING: SYNOPSIS  Diderot's interest i n painting and sculpture cannot be  separated  from his interest i n the other fine arts—poetry, music, and theater— since he u t i l i z e d characteristics and terminology from a l l of them i n discussing any one of them.  Thus, i n evaluating painting he seeks,har-  mony, the attribute of music, f a c i a l expression of sentiment and appropriate gesture, deriving from his interest i n theater; and poetry, the mysterious expression or communication of a truth, or the imaginative portrayal of just about anything.  His "Essay on Painting", writ-  ten to follow the Salon of 1?65» sets forth his notions on what painting i s and what i t ought to be.  He insists that the artist as a man  of genius, should be free of rules; then he proceeds to formulate some rules of his own:  that i t i s the duty of the artist to render  virtue palatable, to render vice odious, to depict a great maxim, to teach a moral lesson, to depict fanaticism, to depict modesty, to display nudes, to cover them up, to be savage, to be sublime.  His  aesthetic ideas neither constitute a unified system nor combine to form a consistent conclusion about the nature of art, because Diderot envisions for i t two internecine roles: and art as propaganda.  art as free expression;  And opposed as he may be to the academic  restrictions imposed upon painting, he nonetheless approaches his subject as a theorist—not just of painting—but of the arts i n general and the cosmos in particular. The "Essay on Painting" was written to follow the Salon of I 7 6 5 , and i t contains many of the ideas already expressed during the course of the four Salons from 1759 through I 7 6 5 .  A familiarity with the  themes and thoughts of this essay w i l l enhance anyone's appreciation of Diderot's commentary on the Salons as well as provide insight into the prejudices and principles he invoked i n evaluating art.  THE ESSAY ON PAINTING:  I765  Nature, which Diderot w i l l later stipulate as the model for a l l painting, appears at the beginning of the essay as the personification of self-sufficiency and benignity: La nature ne fait rien d'incorrect. Toute forme, belle ou laide, a sa cause; et, de tous les etres qui existent, i l n'y a pas un qui ne soit comme i l doit S t r e J This i s not so much to say that all's right with the world, but that, more accurately, Diderot reflects a dominant ideal of his time—that Nature i s coherent, that Nature makes a sense unto herself, and that ultimately, a l l the answers can be found-there.  Having renounced  the principles of religion as a basis for man's participation i n the eternal, Diderot must invoke Nature i n i t s stead with the artist as intercessor and oracle, with art as the translation of the e t e r n a l — whether i t be the true, the good, the beautiful, or a l l three—into human terms.  The substitution i s incomplete, however, because Dide-  rot does not admit of the possibility of a spiritual role or content for art, instead o f — o r alongside—an  aesthetic one.  Nature as the model for art i s nothing new,  of course; the idea,  i n fact, i s a commonplace i n a variety of schools of thought, represented by Aristotle, Democritus, Lucretius, Seneca, Cicero, Marcus Aurelius, Leonardo, and Dante.  Ever since Aristotle delivered nim-  self of the famous judgment that art i s the imitation of Nature, mimesis—the imitation or representation of Nature—became the canon of art not only for the ancient Greeks but for countless generations to come. Having established—or, more accurately, retained—Nature as the model, Diderot proceeds to treat of color and characterizes as f o l lows one who has a feeling for color: Celui qui a le sentiment v i f de l a couleur, a les yeux attaches sur sa t o i l e ; sa bouche est entr'ouverte; i l halete; sa palette est 1'image du chaos. C'est dans ce chaos qu'il trempe son pinceau; et i l en t i r e l'oeuvre de l a creation . . .3 Even granting a l l the indulgences of poetic licence, this characterization requires quite a bit of sympathy to accept l i t e r a l l y ; i t s implications, however, may prove to be of more assistance i n assessing Diderot's c r i t i c a l values; f i r s t , this characterization of the artist indicates Diderot's genuine f l a i r for the agonistic—not only i n the finished artistic production but i n i t s creation as well—an attitude which he develops further i n his Salon commentaries.  But even beyond revealing his f l a i r for the agonistic, this  image of the artist reveals Diderot's notion of the artist as a lonely and sensitive individual—a free spirit—whose existence comprises the pursuit and subsequent rendering of an ideal.  He does  not, at this point, go on to state whether that ideal i s moral or aesthetic, social or a r t i s t i c . The phenomenon of "false color" i s , according to Diderot, the inevitable result of copying the work of masters and not nature, since the artist ceases thereby to use his own  eyes.  Although he often proclaims his ideas i n thunderous prose,  Diderot nevertheless shows occasional indications of an awareness of his limitations as a pundit on art, which i s especially evident i n some of the half-serious chapter t i t l e s i n the essay, such as:  "Mes  pensles bizarres sur le dessin."; "Mes petites id^es sur l a couleur."; "Tout ce que j ' a i compris de ma vie du clair-obscur."; and "Ce que tout l e monde sait sur T*expression, et quelque chose que tout l e monde ne sait pas."^ His next section deals with expression, which he defines as the general image of a sentiment.  In this context he sees the inevitable  connection beteeen theater and painting, since a l l the emotions— hatred, anger, curiosity, love, admiration—"paint themselves" on the face, and from this, the formulation that an actor unacquainted with painting i s a bad actor, just as a painter unacquainted acting i s bad.^  with  In his Salon commentary of 1759, however, he dashes  a painting of "Jason and Medea" quarreling over custody of the c h i l dren, by Carle Van Loo—no less a personage than Director of the Academy—as being "a theatrical decoration i n a l l i t s falsity".''' P  Every station i n l i f e has i t s own character and i t s own expression, servants and soldiers, concubines and kings; savages l i v e without laws and without prejudices, and their features should, therefore, be vigorous and pronounced; the task of the artist, then, i s to be as faithful to natural occurrence as possible when depicting representatives of the different stations of l i f e .  Diderot's emphasis  i n this instance i s upon features, facial expression, and the mutual appropriateness of facial expression and circumstance.  But with his  theatrical orientation to facial expression, he neglects appropriate "artistic expression" of which the look of the face i s only an accessory.  Facial expression and gesture are appropriate both to the  theater and to painting, but painting i s fundamentally a medium of color, light, and form, with gradations of emphasis to suit purposes.  expressive  As a result, i t i s usually when the artist i s interested  only i n the physical—rather than the s p i r i t u a l — r e a l i t y , that his emphasis i s on the actuality of the face rather than on the aspects and p i c t o r i a l treatment of that face which reveal the character or soul.  But this oversight on Diderot's part i s the natural conse-  quence of his denial of spiritual values. Every a g e has i t s tastes, and Diderot affirms that his have changed: Des levres vermeilles bien bordees, une bouche entr'ouverte et riante, de belles dents blanches, une demarche libre, le regard assure, une gorge decouverte, de belles grandes joues larges, un nez retrouss6, me faisaient galoper a dix-huit ans. Aujourd'hui que l e vice ne m'est plus bon, et que je ne suis plus bon au vice, C'est une jeune f i l l e qui a l ' a i r decent et modeste, l a demarche composee, le regard timide, et qui marche en silence a" c6t6 de sa mere, qui m'arrSte et me charme.9 Keeping i n mind Diderot's stated preference for virtue and modesty, his retraction of i t seven pages later i s , i f not exactly surprising, at least worthy of note i n expressing his thought that a trace of paganism must be present i n any representation of the Divinity, without which i t w i l l be cold and empty:  He laments that i f our r e l i -  gion weren't a sad, f l a t metaphysics, i f our painters and sculptors could compare with those of the Ancients, i f our priests weren't stupid bigots, i f this abominable Christianity hadn't been established by murder and blood, i f the joys of our paradise weren't reduced to an impertinent beatific vision of who-knows-what, i f h e l l offered more than gulfs of f i r e , hideous gothic demons, and gnashing teeth, i f our paintings could be of scenes other than those of  atrocity and disgusting butchery, i f our ideas of modesty hadn't proscribed the sight of arms, thighs, breasts, etc., i n the s p i r i t of mortification; i f artists and poets weren't enchained by frightening words of sacrilege and profanation, i f Mary had been the Mother of Pleasure or i f — a s Mother of God—it had been her beautiful eyes, breasts, and hips that attracted the Holy Spirit to her; i f Magdalene had had a love affair with Christ; i f at the wedding Christ had, between wines, explored the bosom of one of the bridesmaids and St. John's bottom, wondering i f he would remain faithful to John; how different our painters, sculptors, and poets would be, with what a different tone we would speak of the charms which played such a great and marvelous role i n the history of our r e l i gion and of our God; with what a different eye we would look at the beauty to which we owe our birth, the incarnation of the Saviour, 10  and the grace of our redemption.  Diderot's vision of the world-  sine e-Eden turned upside-down i s , to say the least, extraordinary, not so much because i t represents the nadir of taste and a rather embarrassingly dogged prurience, but because he sees i n Christian mythology so many more voluptuous possibilities than i t actually delivers; so that i t appeals neither to his reason nor to his senses. This subject is, of course, close to Diderot's heart, and his breathlessness comes through in his style.  One i s tempted to observe that  the passage i s longer than the Begats, but without the suspense. There i s suspense, however: where, oh where, i s the independent clause?  Not even a serpent for comic r e l i e f .  One i s at a loss to evaluate Diderot's conviction on the question of Christian art and i t s inferiority to ancient art, when con-  fronted with his remark from the Salon of 17&3  5  Qu'on me dise, apres cela, que notre mythologie prSte moins st l a peinture que celle des Anciensl Peut-§tre l a Fable off re-1-elle plus de sujets doux et agreables; peut-Stre n'avons-nous rien 3. comparer, en ce genre, . . .mais l e sang que 1'abominable croix a f a i t couler de tous cote's est bien d'une autre ressource pour le pinceau tragique.^ I f the function of art i s — a s i t was for the theater—to teach virtue and extoll morality, the pictorial display of fanaticism would surely have the didactic function of teaching tolerance by inverse example: Etale-moi les scenes sanglantes du fanatisme. It would also have an aesthetically pleasing dramatic quality: Les crimes que l a f o l i e du Christ a commis et fait commetire sont autant de grands drames et bien d'une autre d i f f i c u l t y que l a descente d'Orphee aux enfers . . J 3 But for a l l i t s dramatic quality, i t would s t i l l lack that pagan savor and the pragmatist i n Diderot i s once again at odds with the pagan aesthete i n him: Pour notre paradis, j'avoue qu'il est aussi plat que ceux qui 1'habitent et l e bonheur qu'ils y gotitent. Nulle comparaison entre nos saints, nos apOtres et nos vierges tristement extasies, et ces banquets de l'Olympe . . .Sans contredit j'aime mieux voir l a croupe, l a gorge et les beaux bras de Venus que l e triangle mysterieux; mais ou est, la-dedans, le sujet tragique que je cherche? . . .Jamais aucune religion ne fut aussi f^conde en crimes que le christianisme . . .pas une ligne de son histoire qui ne soit ensanglantee. C'est une belle chose que-le crime et dans 1'histoire et dans l a poesie, et sur l a toile et sur l e marbre.  Diderot feels, then, that nothing i s instructive which does not f i r s t appeal to the senses; which i n turn creates a dilemma whose only possible resolution os not pictorially feasible: tent; nudes for form.  Christianity for con-  Appealing i t might be, but for instruction,  one would have to look elsewhere.  As desiderata, Diderot can neither  reconcile nor choose between homely and modest portrayals of v i r t u e — all, the more necessary, having discarded the spiritual principles of religion—and his equally zealous relish for Olympian flesh and Christian blood.  The polarity i s at work throughout the Salon commentaries  as well, where Diderot, transcending consistency, lavishes praise upon the neo-classical taxidermy of Vien and at the same time, upon the homiletic confections of Greuze.  And i n I78I, after the last of the  Salons, he w i l l write that he would gladly forego the pleasures of seeing beautiful nudities i f he could hasten the moment when painting and sculpture and the other fine arts would inspire virtue and purify morals. II me semble que j ' a i assez vu de tetons et de fesses; ces objets seauisants contrarient 1'emotion de l'Sme, par l e trouble qu'ils jettent dans les sens J 5 Un tableau, une statue licencieuse est peut-Stre plus dangereuse qu'un mauvais l i v r e ; l a premiere, de ces imitations est plus voisine de l a chose.^° In spite of the fact that the above two quotations stand as a disclaimer to Diderot's fondness for marble, canvas, and poetic flesh, they connot be taken as a retraction of that fondness, but simply as the underside of a continuing and circular dialogue between pragmatic moral principles and a Graeco-Roman love of pleasure. no clear-cut understanding  Since  of Diderot's c r i t i c a l values can be  drawn from such inconsistency—except for the fact that his values alternate between the pleasure-loving and the puritanical—one must look beyond the contradictions' to find an underlying concern; this w i l l prove to be more productive of a positive conception of his value judgments—namely, that as a c r i t i c , Diderot i s s t i l l a philosophe, and he remains consistently and fundamentally more concerned with subject matter than with artistic technique, more concerned with what the artist has done than with how or why he did i t , more concerned—in other words—with practical than with aesthetic considerations.  Were he to approach painting from an internal and  structural standpoint rather than from an external and subjective one, the conflict would quickly lose i t s focus and his values would no longer do violence to each other.  Whereas the twentieth-century  observer might seek a truth concealed beneath the appearances, the eighteenth-century philosophe focuses his concern upon the appearances themselves; and those appearances, as we know, appeal by turns to his social consciousness and to his sensitivity to beauty. In the essay section on composition, Diderot sets forth his ideas on subject matter, arrangement, and general tone.  Once again,  we can see that his concern i n this regard does not center upon composition as a structural element but as an illustrational one: That the "expression" of a painting (presumably this means the sentiment or idea expressed), can be f o r t i f i e d through the use of accessories, Diderot illustrates with an example wherein an old gnarled tree outside a cottage would, by i t s presence and form, convey an impression of the inhabitant of the cottage.  This kind  of subtlety i s , unfortunately, not consistently present throughout'  his prescriptions on composition.  His fondness for virtue-building  brush-work, and his dictum that the canvas must present—or t e l l — a moral lesson a l l but excludes the possible exercise of any imagination; the "statement" of the tableau must be clear, and the idea must be moral; i t must say something to him and there must be no doubt on his mind of what i t i s saying. . . . i l faut encore que ton idee a i t juste et consequente, et que tu l'aies rendue s i nettement que je ne m'y meprenne pas, ni moi, ni les autres, ni ceux qui sont a present, ni ceux qui viendront apres. 17  One antithesis of this statement occurred i n I763 when he wrote i n a tone of exasperation, having just seen a kaleidoscopic canvas by Boucher: Entre tant de details, . . .I'oeil ne sait ou s'arr e t e r . . .Quand on e'crit, f a u t - i l tout ecrire? quand on peint, f a u t - i l tout peindre? De grtce, laissez quelque chose a supplier par mon imagintion. Despite the apparent contradiction here—and this i s not to minimize the fact that a contradiction does e x i s t — a closer examination w i l l reveal an explanation more basic than the fact that Diderot cannot make up his mind.  In seeking a solution, we are confronted once  again with his dual set of values—the aesthetic or sensuous and the practical:  the problem i s not necessarily that he cannot decide  between f r i v o l i t y and profundity—but simply that one set of values w i l l not do for the understanding or discussion of both types of painting.  He retains one set of values for the depiction of virtue;  this i s no place for implicit statements—they must be, rather, so obvious that the man of the street can understand them.  The more  sensuous themes c a l l up the other value system; such themes have no need to be explicit; they are calculated to appeal to the senses and not to the mind; they must s t i r the imagination, whereas "moral" painting must leave no room for doubt.  Taken alone i n i t s context,  then, his statement from the essay that what i s on canvas should not be equivocal or indecisive, i s dogmatic, does not allow for extenuating circumstances, has, therefore, very limited application, and comes back to haunt him whenever he feels the need for imagination.  For this reason, Diderot's criticisms of art can be understood  more clearly through his values as implied i n the "Essay" than through his values as stated therein. Affinities of ideas, he suggests, w i l l determine the appropriate accessories for the painting: a violent wind, for example, i s appropriate to a painting of ruins, since i t would suggest the v i c i s situdes of l i f e and the ephemeral nature of man and his endeavors. This perception i s a valid one, and although during the course of the Salons, he often praises paintings of ruins that are nothing so much as paintings of ruins, his idea i s sound and i n 1781, after the last of the Salons, he w i l l write again that i f the painting of ruins does not remind him of the vicissitudes of l i f e and the vanity of the works of man, the painter has created nothing but a formless pile of stones.^9 Continuing his discussion of composition and accessories, he supposes a tomb as the central figure of a painting; a traveller and his dog w i l l be resting on i t s steps, a woman w i l l s i t there nursing a child, and other travellers w i l l stop and read the inscription on the tomb while their horses browse on daisies.  The intent i n this  instance i s to convey the notion that l i f e i s a voyage and the tomb  a place of rest.  But here also the subtlety of his early suggestions  on accessories i s gone; even to an eighteenth-century mind, the presence of a tomb carries with i t s rather dark dignity the equally dark susceptibility to desecration.  This desecration could be as  fortuitous as pigeon-droppings or as ludicrous as Diderot has envisioned i t :  the roosting of master and dog and the nursing of a  child on the steps of a tomb conveys roughly the same impression as the sight of a bust of Beethoven sporting a fedora.  As for the  tomb and i t s significance, Diderot would have painting become the medium of the cliche, expressing i t s e l f i n hackneyed symbols; i f , as he says i n the Salon of 176l,^° the sight "of ruins and tombs should inspire reverie and melancholy, he should also have been aware, concerned as he was with taste, that a failure to use that faculty judiciously could also result i n catastrophe; to Diderot, this tableau might connote repose; to others, a rather distasteful glimpse of the end of the t r a i l .  This i s one flaw i n singling out  painting as the medium for communicating pithy maxims and pious saws: the same painting w i l l convey different "maxims" to different p e o p l e — i f i t successfully conveys any at all—depending entirely upon the personal experience and perceptive awareness of the beholder.  For this reason, art cannot be a didactic medium and re-  main art: instead.  i t ceases to be expression and becomes illustration Paintings, for many of the people who look at them, are  either pretty or ugly.  Diderot has apparently glimpsed an idea of  this nature when he says toward the end of the same-essay:  Et quelle difference encore de l a sensation de l'homme ordinaire a celle du philosophel^l  He has recognized the possible difference i n degrees of perception, but he never fully grasps—or acknowledges—its implications, whether of the ultimate or inevitable fate i t spells for his envisioned pedagogic painting or of the possibilities i t suggests for the positive and instructive role of a c r i t i c .  The man who i s insensitive to  nature, moreover, w i l l likewise be insensitive to art, further restricting the scope of didactic effectiveness: La nature, n i l'art qui l a copie, ne disent rien a l'homme stupide ou froid, peu de chose & l'homme i g norant . But Diderot merely encounters the difficulty, mentions i t , and moves on without altering his idea of the artist as instructor. His next point i s that the painting of a theatrical scene—that i s , of a stage and a c t o r s — i s insufferable and nothing short of cruel satire.  In the arts of imitation, there must, be something savage,  brutal, striking, and vast, .but there should be no mixture, i n painting, of real and allegorical figures which, he says, gives to history the aura of a "conte". -^ 2  Following Diderot's reasoning i n this  case by applying what we know of his dual value system, we may presume that he means that the interposition of imaginary figures--no matter how real may be the qualities they represent—detracts from the explicit statement required of an historical painting.  Unless  the allegorical figures i n question wear their t i t l e s like banners across their respective chests, there i s room for interpretation of just who or what they may be.  We may understand from this that Di-  derot's insistence upon the purity of the genre derives not from aesthetic but from very practical considerations. Painting has i n common with poetry the fact that i t must contain  morals. ^  Sixteen years later, he would mention poetry, this time  with reference to taste i n general: On retrouve les poetes dans les peintres, et les peintres dans les poetes.^5 . This, i n turn, i s reminiscent of Leonardo's statement: Painting i s poetry which i s seen and not heard, and poetry i s painting which i s heard but not seen.^ 0  Diderot goes on to remind everyone who takes up pen, brush, or chisel, that their goal i s to render virtue attractive, vice repulsive; to celebrate great actions, to honor wounded virtue, to assail unscathed vice, and to frighten t y r a n t s ^ — i n short, by carrying the 7  implications to their logical conclusion—to f u l f i l l the functions of secular priests. Demanding to see spread before him bloody scenes of fanaticism, Diderot exhorts artists thereby to show both to sovereigns and to populace what they can expect from the "sacred preachers of l i e s " , saying that while the figures themselves may be mute, they make him pQ speak with himself.  This alone might be considered as the  raison d'Jitre for a l l art—the inducement to contemplation—but Diderot does not use i t i n that context, because for him, as we have seen, art needs not so much a raison d ' e t r e as i t does a pract i c a l application. Having dictated some principles of imitative art, Diderot casts another sidelong glance at antiquity:  he reflects that nudes,  which were associated at that time with the classical and rococo styles and content, recall a remote, a simpler and more innocent age, with untamed morals, more appropriate to the arts of imita-  tion. 9 2  The natural state, with i t s "untamed morals" connotes drama  to Diderot—that arresting and absorbing quality that also, ideally, stimulates the imagination and at the same time instructs the mind; but the transition from theory to practice w i l l show the very real d i f f i c u l t y of portraying innocence, simplicity, nudity, and savagery — w i t h a moral lesson thrown i n — a l l on one canvas.  Instructive : art  must, of course, appeal to the mind, but i t i s useless i f no one pays i t the slightest heed, hence the need for some arresting dramatic quality; the d i f f i c u l t y of the theory lies once again i n i t s pract i c a l application:  the dramatic and poetic qualities required to  lure the observer into enlightened ways conflict directly .with explicit  statement.  The sensualist then yields to the pragmatist as Diderot asks: Mais que signifient tous ces principes, s i l e gout est une chose de caprice, et s ' i l n'y a aucune regie eternelle, immuable, du beau? Si l e gout est une chose de caprice, s ' i l n'y a aucune regie du beau, d'ou viennent done ces emotions . . .qui forcent de nos yeux les pleurs de l a joie, de l a douleur, de 1'admiration . . .  ?30  Diderot r e a l i z e s — a t times, as this example shows—that emotion cannot be evoked or explained according to rule.  In this instance, he  attempts to integrate emotions and aesthetics, to approximate sens i t i v i t y and intellect, and to understand one i n terms of the elements of the other.  Taste i s indeed a capricious thing, conditioned  by many factors of background.  But what disturbs Diderot i n this  example i s not so much the unpredictability of taste i t s e l f as the fact that he sometimes likes paintings which his principles indicate he ought not to like at a l l .  Diderot goes on, i n the next paragraph,  to attempt to define the aesthetic qualities by associating them i n  a context: Le vrai, le bon et le beau se tiennent de bien prds. Ajouter a l'une des deux premieres qualites quelque circonstance rare, e'clatante, et le vrai sera beau, et l e bon sera beau.-^ Having established the context, Diderot considers next a definition of taste: Une f a c i l i t e acquise par des experiences re"itere"s, a saisir le vrai ou le bon, avec l a circonstance qui l e rend beau, et d'en etre promptement et vivement tou-  The definition, unfortunately, i s circular, since i t i s constructed from the original unknown quantities; but I t does reveal that i n his insistence on "some rare and striking circumstance", he seeks a dramatic quality i n beauty, rather than a spiritual or moral quality, and yet expects i t to produce a moral effect.  Those with an onto-  genetic turn of mind who want to see a method or at least an evolution in Diderot's thought on this aesthetic troica would not be cheered to find that after sixteen years, i n his "Detached Thoughts on Painting" (1781) only the wording i s changed, and his "aesthetics" s t i l l consists not i n analysis but i n definition: Le beau n'est que le vrai, releve par des circonstances possibles, mais rares et merveilleuses . . .Le bon n'est que 1'utile, releve" par des circonstances possibles et merveilleuses.33 But notions of such ethereal purity can only exist in a vacuum and need, therefore, some rather special referents before they can take on any meaning whatsoever.  The addition of the term "useful", i s ,  therefore, a good stroke i n that i t brings things once more earth-  ward, but as a pragmatic value, simply inserted, i t i s inadequate to lend meaning or give real focus to the aesthetic values.  The  passage i s significant, though, i n shoving the dual direction of his thought:  the aesthetic and the pragmatic, the eternal verities  and the temporal.  Diderot loves beauty and virtue, but he loves  productivity and usefulness with equal zeal; as a result, he has tried to work productivity into that vast scheme of temporal and eternal verities, but as argument, as definition, and as logic, i t does not withstand examination.  The continuing, circular dialogue  between mundane and ethereal values does, however, give insight into the confusion—that for more than twenty years existed i n his mind — a s to the nature of art, the role of aesthetics, and their relationship to moral values.. Sensitivity i s , of course, necessary to taste, but i t can also be a hindrance, according to Diderot; the capacity for discernment diminishes with increasing sensitivity, since a person possessed of extreme sensitivity i s moved by everything. In this case, reason can be helpful i n rectifying a hasty judgment, but the conclusion of his essay i s that the only way to appreciate a work of genius i s to compare i t immediately with Nature, and that the only one who knows how to do that i s another man of genius.^  This i s  not altogether satisfying as a conclusion; on the other hand, there i s , perhaps, no reason to suppose that i t i s a conclusion rather than simply another idea that happens to appear at the end of the essay.  At any rate, he seems to be relegating art' to the tender  mercies of genius, both for giving i t i t s original content and for truly appreciating the merit of that content.  His formula of "com-  paring i t immediately with Nature" i s characteristically vague, and  i t i s d i f f i c u l t to determine whether he i s prescribing a resemblance to actual natural occurrence, or whether instead he simply means that the work of art i s not something that can be understood on i t s own terms, but which must be experienced i n a context larger than i t s e l f before i t can have meaning. I t does not require a genius, however, to condemn or praise a painting s t r i c t l y according to the degree of resemblance i t bears to "real l i f e " .  For many  people this might be the only criterion i n judging a painting, but as with his essay, Diderot's Salon commentaries w i l l show that he does not limit himself to this, or any other, single criterion; renderings of Olympian dalliance and f r o l i c which are mythological rather than real or natural, often move him to warm applause. Perhaps the clearest means of understanding Diderot's use of the word—and the concept— of Nature i s by considering i t as a designation and principle, representing an alternative to formulated rules as a standard of judgment, even though the "formulated rules" remain, for the most part, unspecified. His insistence upon nature as model arises as much from the influence of classical writers and currently popular ideas as from Diderot's impatience with what he might c a l l academic art; but the Academy remains a favorite target, with whose products he contrasts the daily experience of l i f e which, "through i t s subtle calculations, creates elements of geometry that the Academy could never grasp."35  The Academy repre-  sents for Diderot the omnibus category for a monolith of atrophy, intolerance, and reaction; yet nearly a l l the painters whose paintings he discussed i n the Salon commentaries were members of the Academy i n one capacity or another.  Some he liked; some he dis-  liked; nevertheless, Diderot's broadsides against "academic art"  remained broad, and his grievances were never specified.  Sixteen  years later, i n his "Detached Thoughts on Painting", he asks Aristotle's pardon, and submits that i t i s vicious criticism to deduce exclusive rules from perfect works, as i f there weren't an i n f i n i t y of ways to please.-^  He i s not this tolerant i n actual practice,  but his constitutional distaste for rules as strictures remains constant.  As constant as his pragmatism; because later i n the same  essay he states that no art can reach any degree of perfection without practice and without a large number of public schools of drawing and design.3?  Diderot disliked formulated rules and yet, i n  nearly every paragraph throughout, the essay,* he has attempted either to formulate rules of his own or to apply notions he already accepts; the difference i s that they are of a personal—and not of an i n s t i tutional—nature.  Nevertheless, i n proposing schools of drawing  and design as a solution to the problem of creating a viable national art similar to that of the Ancients, Diderot f a i l s to see that technique, as an educational commodity, i s much easier to manage than inspiration; that the tension between spontaneity and standardization—between the natural and the academic—cannot be alleviated by more and better institutions, but must eventually be resolved within the individual artist, because i t i s he--and not the rulethumping theoretician—who i s the only rapport between the thought and the image.  THE SALONS:  1759-1781  DIDEROT'S TASTE AND METHOD  Diderot's commentaries on the biennial Salons of the Academy were destined for the Correspondance l i t t e r a i r e , a miscellaneous i n formative sheet circulated to t i t l e d francophiles i n Germany, Sweden, Poland, and Russia by his friend Grimm, a German-Parisian man of letters who made a profession of collecting—for his select subscribers—notes of literary and a r t i s t i c events i n Paris.  These art ex-  hibitions had been established i n 17371 i n a "sense freeing art from the confines of the Academy, and exposing i t to the public. The Correspondance l i t t e r a i r e which contained Diderot's commentaries,'' however, was not published until 1812 and thus had no immediate i n fluence within his own country. The relatively brief and sketchy Salon of 1759 coincides with Diderot's novitiate as an art c r i t i c .  The Salons of.±76l, &3» ^5t  and 67 are much longer, and treatment of paintings discussed i s i n creasingly thorough with the passing years.  Their length prompted  Grimm to complain and to urge his friend to abbreviate his comments and observations, since a l l had to be copied again by hand once they were received. Diderot, who claimed to be suffering from the l a s s i tude of encroaching age, said that Grimm's request would be an easy matter to arrange.  He was also busy with other projects, and the  Salons from I769 to 1781 are accordingly brief. Not only do Diderot's Salon commentaries provide us with a contemporary view of the art of his time and with an illustration of his  progress and d i f f i c u l t i e s i n becoming a c r i t i c , but they also serve as concrete illustrations of the application of his c r i t i c a l values which underlay the principles enumerated i n his "Essay".  The sub-  stance of those principles might be summarized as follows:  (1)  Nei-  ther formulated rules nor the paintings of other masters—but Nature i t s e l f — must be the model for art; this i s not so much a c a l l for realism, i n the s t y l i s t i c sense,: as i t i s a plea for a r t i s t i c freedom from the strictures of rules.  (2)  The artist i s a man of genius;  (but this idealized attitude does not cause Diderot to approach the paintings of the Academy painters with anything resembling deference or awe).  (3)  Christianity i s insipid, on  the one hand, offering  nothing to appeal to the senses; on the other hand, i t i s a veritable a r t i s t i c wellspring with i t s ruck of episodes dealing i n fanaticism and bloodshed, whose explicit depiction would pit the practice of Christianity against i t s e l f by disgusting i t s followers and leading them away—a translation, i n effect, from superstition to knowledge. (^)  Cold, stupid, or ignorant people w i l l neither receive nor under-  stand the intended message.  (5)  disseminate moral ideology.  From his discussions i n connection with  A l l artists have a social duty to  these principles, we may conclude that Diderot has a dual set of values and envisions a dual, and conflicting, role for a r t — a s free expression and as propaganda—that  i s , as a medium for the diffusion  of ideas. The concept of u t i l i t y , which i s fundamental to his system of values, does not appear " o f f i c i a l l y " — t h a t i s as a formulation— u n t i l l ? 8 l i n his sequel to the Salons, the "Detached Thoughts on Painting".  But while u t i l i t y may not yet have been formulated as  a principle for the judgment of painting, i t appeared as a value—an unspecified or unnamed c r i t e r i o n — i n many of his critiques.  Having formulated these principles bearing on the subject matter of painting, Diderot does not on that account remain bound by them. As general observations and opinions, they have l i t t l e potential for specific application, but the value systems that formed them can be seen to be at work i n his "capricious taste".  By the time Diderot  wrote the "Essai", moreover, he had covered four Salons as Grimm's Parisian correspondent, but i n the beginning—in 1759—his theoretical preparation was literary and his technical preparation practically nonexistent.  Such a lacuna does not make him a philistine by any  means, but i t s existence does explain why so often his critiques seem more to be reactions than judgments. On the mother hand, the spontaneous candor of " I don't like i t " cannot be dismissed ungratefully.. The paintings discussed i n this section were chosen because (1) they form a representative sampling of the various genres exhibited i n the Salons and show Diderot's c r i t i c a l method at work i n a varied yet restricted field, and (2)  illustrate, through their several ex-  amples that Diderot does not proceed from a standpoint of structure, theme, or style, to understand the paintings i n terms of the idiom of the a r t i s t .  SELECTED COMMENTARIES  Although some apologists would present.Diderot to the world as a humble, well-meaning, magnanimous c r i t i c who looked for beauty i n stead of faults, they do so by camouflaging the abundantly-illustrated fact that he was also a master of insult, an ability which probably owed the candor of i t s expression to i t s anonymity.  The humility i s  reserved for opening and concluding remarks to each Salon, but the merciless apostrophes and asides are an integral part of the text, as a chronological survey w i l l show: Voici, mon ami, les ide'es qui m'ont pass6 par l a t§te a l a vue des tableaux qu'on a exposes cette annee au Salon. II y en aura de vraies, il y en aura de fausses. Tant8t vous me trouverez trop sevdre, tantot trop i n dulgent. (Introduction., Salon l ? 6 l ) 1 (Of J.-B. Pierre) Je ne sais ce que cet homme devient. II est riche; i l a eu de 1 Education; il a fait le voyage de Rome; on dit qu'il a de l'esprit; rien ne le presse de f i n i r un ouvrage: d'ou vient done l a mediocrity de 2 presque toutes ses compositions? (Text, Salon r ? 6 l ) Oui, j'aimerais mieux perdre un doigt que de contrister d'honnetes gens qui se sont e'puises de fatigue pour nous plaire. (Conclusion, Salon 1 7 6 3 ) ^ Parce qu'un tableau n'aura pas f a i t notre admiration, f a u t - i l qu'il devienne l a honte et l e supplice de l'artiste? (Conclusion, Salon 1 7 6 3 ) ^ Qu'un morceau de t o i l e soit barbouille" ou qu'un cube de marbre soit gtt6, qu'est-ce que cette perte en comparaison du soupir amer qui s'Schappe du coeur de l'homme afflige? (Conclusion, Salon 1 7 6 3 ) ^ Re"servons notre fouet pour les m6chants, les dangereux, les ingrats, les hypocrites, les concussionnaires, les tyrans, les fanatiques, et les autres. fl£aux du genre humain. (Conclusion, Salon I763) Cela est miserable . . .Cachez-moi cela, M. Halle: on diroit que vous avez barbouille" cette t o i l e d'une glace aux pistaches. (Text, Salon I765) Vous venez a* temps, Chardin, pour reorder mes yeux que votre confrere Challe avoit mortellement a f f l i ges. (Text, Salon 17&5)  Voici mes critiques et mes eloges. Je loue, je blame d'apres ma sensation particuliere qui ne f a i t pas l o i . Dieu ne demanderoit de nous que l a sincerity avec nousmSmes. Les artistes voudront bien n'Stre pas plus exigeants. (Introduction, Salon 1 7 6 7 ) 9 Le f i l s de Vernet est un des pointus les plus rddoutables. I I entre au Sallon. II voit deux tableaux. II demande de qui i l s sont. On l u i repond de Halle; et i l ajoute vous en. Allez vous en. Cela est aussi bien jug£ que mal d i t . Je vous le repete sans pointe; M. Halle, s i vous n'en scavez pas faire davantage, allezvous en. (Text, Salon I767) 10  Monsieur Baudouin, vous me rappellez l'abbe Cossart, cure de St-Remi & Dieppe. Un jour qu'il etait monte a l'orgue de son €glise, i l mit par hazard l e pied sur une pedale, 1'instrument r£sonna, et le cure Cossart s'ecria: 'Ahl ahl je joue de l'orgue; cela n'est pas s i d i f f i c i l e que je croyais.' M. Baudouin, vous avez mis l e pied sur l a pedale, et puis c'est tout. (Text, Salon 176?)  T 1  (Of "Head of an Old Man" by Fragonard) M. Fragonard, quand on s'est f a i t un nom, i l faut avoir un peu plus d amour-propre. (Text, Salon I767)' 1  2  I t i s easy to see that sometimes he i s mordant, and sometimes his prose rings with a l l the fervor of a malevolent revivalist-goneberserk.  And i t suggests that the c r i t i c a l profession was deprived  of one of i t s most picturesque and engaging devices by the advent of l i b e l legislation.  But Diderot had no personal axe to grind with the  painters themselves, and his commentaries were not intended for reading by the general public. He even shows traces of a live-and-letl i v e turn of mind i n the observation that just because a painting has not pleased us, i t ought not necessarily to be the shame of the painter.  But Diderot approaches art as a philosophe with a l l the i n -  clinations of a social reformer whose program does not leave much room—in the actual practice of art c r i t i c i s m — f o r a tolerant  relativity.  An exemplary object of Diderot's revolving i r e i s Bou-  cher who, i n I765, succeeded Van Loo as director of the Academy. He was a fashionable painter of the time who catered to social climbers and courtesans with fleshy, i d y l l i c scenes.  It was useless to look  to Boucher for a moral, of course, because his real subjects were charm and prettiness; he was a first-rate painter i n a second-rate genre—wish fulfillment.  In the course of twenty years, Diderot's  opinion of him has come f u l l - c i r c l e : Quelles couleursI quelle variete"! quelle richesse d'objets et d'idgesl Cet homme a tout, exceote l a verite. (176l)'3 . . .ceux qui sont etrangers au vrai gout, & l a verity, aux idees justes, =L l a se*verite de 1'art. Comment resisteraient-ils au saillant, aux pompons, aux nudites, au libertinage, a" l'epigramme de Boucher? . . .Les gens d'un grand gofit, d'uji gout severe et antique, n'en font nul cas. ( I 7 6 I ) ' 1  Et puis une confusion d'objets entasses les uns sur les autres, s i de"place"s, s i disparates, que c'est moins le tableau d'un homme sense que le reve d'un fou. (I765) ^ J'ose dire que cet homme ne sait vraiment ce que c'est que l a grtce; j'ose dire qu'il n'a jamais connu l a verite"; j'ose dire que les id<5es de delicatesse, de l'honnetete, d'innocence, de simplicitd, l u i sont devenues presqu'e'trangdres . . .qu ' i l n'a pas vu un instant l a nature . . .qu'il est sans goftt. (17&5) J'ai dit trop de mal de Boucher; je me retracte.  (1781)  17  Having given a moment to a survey of Diderot's inconsistencies, i t i s time for an examination of his method.  The modern reader may  avail himself of illustrated editions of Diderot's text, but Grimm's subscribers could not, and as a result, most of the critiques begin  with a routine description of the painting: who or what i s placed at l e f t or right, foreground or background. the judgment.  After the description,  A l l his notions, from his admiration for the Ancients  to his appreciation of f i l i a l virtue occur, regroup, and intermingle i n the course of the critiques. Summing up his Salon commentaries for the f i r s t session, 1759t Diderot sighs, "How amazing the Ancients are!" " A l l design and no idea." 18  And the Moderns?  Diderot maintained from the beginning  of the f i r s t Salon, that there was more to painting than arranging figures, that the f i r s t and most important thing was to find a great idea; he accorded the artistic virtue of idea to the Ancients, seeing l i t t l e more than wall decoration i n what was before him.  But  the important consideration here i s to understand the terms of Diderot's comparison: none existed.  he had never seen any ancient painting, since  At the time of the 1759 Salon, moreover, the Roman  frescoes and mosaics at Pompeii and Herculaneum were s t i l l relatively unknown, since Winckelmann s famous work publicizing and 1  praising them did not appear i n print u n t i l 176^.  Accordingly,  Diderot's notion of ancient art was necessarily limited to sculpture:  to Roman copies and Roman originals as well as to his per-  sonal idea—derived from xri.de reading of classical x^rriters—of what ancient art must have been like.  But i n ancient times, the word  was more highly esteemed than the image, and even during the Middle Ages, painting was one of the crafts, superintended by the guilds, and not an "art".  Diderot's judgment, therefore, i s based  on an essentially unknown quantity: art.  the real nature of ancient  The quality, real or imagined, that he seems to cherish  above a l l i n "ancient art" i s not sublimity of execution but  sublimity of concept, with an exclusive emphasis on an intellectual idea. In I76I, Diderot praises a bust of Falconet; the two adjectives—and, presumably, c r i t e r i a — a r e "beau" and "ressemblant" J 9 v  S t i l l , he says, art should be sublime, not just tolerable, and the best way to get at that i s to disdain French costumery; Grimm's appended comment i n I76I contains the further observation that to sculpt a child i n French costume i s a cursed, f l a t thing befitting a barbarian or Gothic sculptor.  Such calculated arrogance i n art  i s harmful to any pretentions to the sublime, unless the word and concept of sublime connote only that clothes make the man.  In  comparing the French with the Ancients, then, Diderot was essen-' t i a l l y comparing painting with sculpture, which i s not quite f a i r . But the comparison goes beyond that:  Diderot's admiration for the  Ancients i s an affair of the heart—and head—even though i t i s not based on an accurate idea of ancient art; he i s drawn more to the historical or literary person than to the qualities of the image as art: Qui est-ce qui attache vos regards sur un buste de Marc-Aur&le ou de Trajan, de Seneque ou de Cic^ron? Est-ce le merite de ciseau de 1 ' a r t i s t e ou 1'admiration de l'homme? . . . i l faut qu'un portrait soit ressemblant pour moi, et bien peint pour l a post6rit<§.21 Another misconception Diderot brought with him into the Salons was of the nature of the so-called creative process i t s e l f .  We have  already seen one characterization drawn from his "Essay on Painting" of 1 7 ^ 5 »  which conveys an unfortunate image of the artist i n a l l  his grape-eyed, slack-jawed f r a i l t y , daubing away.  His rendering  of the Artist i n the Salon of l ? 6 l verges to a lesser degree on  caricature, but i n both cases, the element of caricature i s merely Diderot's way of dramatizing what i n his opinion ought to be the artist's physical and emotional involvement i n the creative process: Avant de prendre son pinceau, i l faut avoir frissonne vingt fois de son sujet, avoir perdu le sommeil, s'fetre leve' pendant l a nuit, et avoir couru en chemise et pieds nus jeter sur le papier ses esquisses a l a lueur d'une lampe de n u i t . ^ 2  Although gymnastics and inspiration do not necessarily coincide, Diderot's concept of the artist plying his art does convey his belief that the artist should be enthusiastic, spontaneous, and never beyond the grips of his "idea".  Realistically speaking, how-  ever, even a session of feverish creativity i s made possible only through an accumulation of knowledge and s k i l l on the  part.of.the  artist, and not through trance-like submission to forces beyond his control. One of the f i r s t paintings he discusses i n 1759 i s "The Bathers" by Carle Van Loo. ** He and other minor artists who labored i n the 2  shadow of Watteau, Chardin, Fragonard, et a l , had found, i n their own work, a visual compromise between the seventeenth-century academic tradition and the demands of the new taste for fantasy and eroticism.  In a moment of largesse, Diderot once said that the •  c r i t i c should suggest improvements i n the work under c r i t i c a l examination, and i n this instance, he i s as good as his word: With regard to the bather on the l e f t (see Fig. 1), he does not like the folded fingers of the hand, and suggests that they be extended or that the face be made to rest on the flat of the hand.  But he has  not looked at i t long enough. I f her hand—with or without the ex-  tended fingers—were moved, i t would throw her entirely off-balance; the resting of her face on her hand would be a theatrical gesture and imply more meaning than the painting actually delivers.  Even  with i t s defects, however, he finds i t to be a "voluptuous tableau", what with the bare feet, the thighs, breasts, and buttocks, and admits that i t i s perhaps not so much the talent of the artist that holds him as i t his own vice. Diderot condemns a monastery scene by Jeurat:  "Carthusians  i n Meditation, " 5 because "it does not'convey his conception 2  of what a monastery scene ought to do to him:  - .ou :  i t lacks silence,  savagery, divine justice, an idea, profound adoration, ecstasy, and terror.  And he suggests that since the painter's imagination has  obviously failed him, he should have gone among the Carthusians to see things first-hand. Despairing of such painters, whose works lack "truth"--in this case, silence, savagery, ecstasy, and terror —Diderot writes: S ' i l y a peu de gens qui sachent regarder un tableau, y a - t - i l bien des peintres qui sachent regarder l a nature? " 2  As a purview of the a r t i s t i c affairs of the time, the question i s profound indeed, but even Nature could hardly produce such a profusion of theatrical moods and r>rops i n one location, as he has specified.  Diderot sometimes condemns theatricality, sometimes  praises i t without naming i t , and sometimes exacts i t when i t i s not there.  The latter point i s i n operation i n his judgment of  "Carthusians". Two years later, i n his discussion of L.-M.  Van Loo's "Por-  t r a i t of the King", ? (Fig.2 ) Diderot suggests that a l l the ermine 2  around the upper part of the figure makes i t seem shorter, and that this i s the wrong kind of clothing to show the majesty of a king. The problem of the artist i n such a case i s to paint a picture of the king that i s , unmistakably, a picture of the king and not, perhaps, a picture of the local grocer who has just won a lottery prize.  The element of majesty must be emphasized while at the  same time pomposity and ostentation must be kept to a minimum or eliminated i f the artist i s to strike that d i f f i c u l t balance between the sublime and the ridiculous.  He accomplishes this p r i -  marily through the use of accessories that are recognizably regal, and ermine i s a standard item i n the royal sartorial paraphernalia, since for centuries i t has symbolized the honor and purity peculiar to the king's exalted station. The ermine, the fleurs de l i s , the scepter, and the stately classical columns i n the background, as well as the presence of the t h r o n e — a l l are accessories which suggest the personage of the king.  Compositionally, however, the ac-  tual person of the king i s more d i f f i c u l t to manage; since kings traditionally wear more clothing than other people anyway, the structural problem i s to make the king look as though he i s actuall y wearing a l l the heavy drapery and not as though he has just emerged from beneath i t , planting his scepter triumphantly terra firma.  on  While ermine i s appropriate kingly garb, therefore,  i t must be handled i n such a way,  compositionally, that i t does not  look as heavy as i t actually i s , and Diderot's objection to i t s heaviness i s well-founded.' The sight of the royal' thigh beneath a l l the yardage of f l u f f i s reassurance that the king i s , i n fact, there; but the mass of drapery on the floor at his l e f t detracts from the verticality that would best serve to convey an impression  of loftiness and majesty:  i t exerts instead a-downward pull and  even the vertical accents of the columns and throne do not preserve the figure of the king from the relentless encroachment of swish-swash.  As for Diderot, i n spite of his objections, he w i l l  l i s t this among the excellent paintings i n his recapitulation of the Salon of l ? 6 l . Concerning I The Publication of the Peace, 1 7 ^ 9 " by Le Romain, 1  Diderot says that he has never approved of mixing real and a l l e gorical figures; that the real ones lose their "verite'" next to the allegorical ones, which i n turn lend an obscurity to the entire composition.  Diderot had an acute distaste "for a l l such paintings,  although he readily admitted to their redeeming qualities, when he could discern any.  Their very obscurity invariably sparked his  imagination to outrageous comparisons which tend to endow the paintings under consideration with much more l i f e than they o r i ginally possessed.  In "Publication", the figure of Peace descends  from the sky to present an olive branch to the king.  Included  among the allegorical figures are Generosity, Discord, and a couple of rivers.  Unimpressed by the awesome pretensions of the subject-  matter, Diderot computes i t s actual, i f not intended,  effect:  On prendrait au premier.coup d'oeil le monarque pour Thds^e qui revient victorieux du Minotaure, ou pluttt pour Bacchus qui revient de l a conqugte de l'Inde; car i l a l ' a i r un peu ivre. Besides creating obscurity of meaning, the juxtaposition of real and allegorical figures detracts from the dignity of the real f i g ures because they appear "flat and ridiculous" while the figures from antique legend or mythology evoke pleasant historical or  literary associations. Finally, this division between real and allegorical figures does violence to the unity of the picture: Le contraste de ces figures antiques et modernes ferait croire que l e tableau est un compose' de deux pieces rapport^es, l'une d'aujourd'hui, et l'autre qui fut peinte i l y a quelque mille ans. 9 Nevertheless, Diderot admires the artist's rendering of certain figures, declares that i t has been painted boldly and forcefully, and advises Grimm not to miss it„ Diderot brings out his big guns for his discussion of J.-B. Pierre's "Descent from the Cross".  (Fig. 3)  He begins with a  lament of Pierre's dogged mediocrity and then finishes him off with an: accusation of plagiarism and a x-jithering comparison with Carrache, who although Diderot gives no further indication as to his identity—was Annibale Carracci, sixteenth-century Italian eclectic who founded a flourishing academy of art at Bologna, and whose a r t i s t i c ambition consisted of establishing a standard for recognizing and formulating what was best i n the art of the past, and of illustrating that standard i n his own work. painting i n question  (Fig. k)  The Carracci  hung i n the Palais-Royal and, Di-  derot submits, was undoubtedly well known to J.-B. Pierre.  Dide-  rot goes on to apostrophize Pierre and to cite the following similarities:  In each painting, the Mother of Christ i s seated; i n  each, she i s dying of grief; a l l the action of the other figures centers upon this grief; the head of the Son rests i n the Mother's lap; the other women are alarmed at the peril of the dying Mother. Diderot's comparison continues with the observation that from the background of Carracci's painting, St.. Anne rushes toward her  daughter screaming, her face a mixture of traces of long-standing sorrow and despair, but that since Pierre has not dared to copy the master to such an extent, he has instead created the same effect by placing an old man i n the background of his picture.  Having  injured Pierre with his enumeration of the similarities between his painting and that of Carracci, Diderot goes on to add insult by considering the differences:  Pierre's Christ looks like the victim  of a drowning or an execution, whereas Carracci's i s f u l l of nobil i t y ; Pierre's Virgin, moreover, i s cold and contorted, compared to Carracci's, and Diderot cites the following properties of Carracci 's Virgin as proof:  Her motionless hand resting on the Son's  chest, her drawn face, fainting air, half-opened mouth, and closed eyes.  After a l l this, Diderot dispatches him with a stern rebuke:  Sachez, monsieur Pierre, qu'il ne faut pas copier, ou copier mieux.30 Actual comparison of the two paintings weakens Diderot's considerably.  accusation  The c r i c i f i x i o n i s a traditional subject i n painting,  as i s the descent, which suffices i n i t s e l f to make accusations of plagiarism rather d i f f i c u l t to substantiate.  Diderot has noticed  that Pierre has placed an old man i n the picture instead of St. Anne, but he has missed two of the most important physical proper-, ties that distinguish Pierre's offering from that of Carracci: (1) the shape—that i s , the actual length/x-jidth dimensions of the canvas—and (2) the presence, i n Pierre's painting, of the cross itself.  Pierre's elongated canvas, combined with the dominating  presence of the cross gives the major emphasis to verticality; whereas the emphasis i n Carracci i s horizontal:  no one i s standing  — a motif which the trees along the horizon repeat abstractly i n their patterns of curved and broken lines.  But the basis of Car-  racci' s design i s i n the emphatic diagonal extending from lower right to upper l e f t and created by the supine inclination of the body of Christ and, i n turn, of His Mother.  The diagonal movement,  then, extends from the feet and cloth at the lower right through Christ and His Mother and stops with the young woman behind her, (presumably the Magdalene), the direction of whose glance carries the eye and the attention to St. Anne who expresses her concern and alarm with the operatic gestures of open mouth and outstretched hands.  The presence of St. Anne and the woman next to her counter-  balance the non-axial placement of the other three figures.  Parallels  and smaller accents of the main diagonal occur i n the placement of the hands of a l l the figures except St. Anne whose hands serve structurally to unify the parallel diagonals formed by the two groups of figures.  The underlying structure of the composition, then, i s  that of an ellipse extending diagonally from lower right to upper left.  But the formal or technical excellence of a painting does  not preserve i t from ruin, and i n the Carracci, the plethora of hands and open mouths casts a wooden theatricality on the gestures and expressions.  The identical positions and expressions of Christ  and His Mother, with their heads t i l t e d back, eyes closed (mercifully), and mouths open conveys no expression of sorrow whatsoever.  The static  quality of strong horizontals may reinforce a statement of sorrow or death, but cannot alone create that statement, and Carracci's juxtaposition of alarmed concern and mass rigor mortis does not create i t either.  There i s i n Carracci, unfortunately, more symmetry than  sincerity, and the structural perfection of the composition i s not accompanied by a corresponding depth of genuine feeling. Pierre's composition i s neither so obvious nor so simple as Carracci's.  The key element of Pierre's design i s the head of the  Magdalene,' or young woman, at the apex of the lower quadrant of the picture.  The upper quadrant i s dominated by the cross, whose pre-  sence i n the middle distance reinforces the central position of the Magdalene by i t s vertical accent on the median line.  The ac-  cessory figures on the l e f t , through the linking patterns of the eae k arms with/other and with the ladder, serve to connect the lower figure group of Christ, His Mother, and the Magdalene with the other dominant figure, which i s the cross. Horizontal accents i n the cross and i n the basin i n the right- foreground emphasize the recumbent position of the body of Christ and i t s counterpart i n the slumped position of His stunned Mother.  Nearly every figure i s  twisted at the waist or shoulders, illustrating an element of design known as contrapposto, which contributes to the overall spiral movement that characterizes the composition, and which even acts upon the cross i t s e l f :  the cross occupies, f i r s t of a l l , a plane which  i s diagonal to the foreground, beginning the twisting movement; on the far side of the cross, the x-and pulls the cloth backward, continuing the twist.  But the contrapposto of the old man, who alone  occupies the right quadrant, repeats inversely the position of the cross, offsets i t s twisting motion, and returns the eye and attention once again from the background of the somber and foreboding sky to the figure group at the foot of the cross. Compositionally, the picture i s a controlled exercise on the part of the artist:  The  psychological focus of the painting i s the Mother of Christ; but from  the standpoint of structure, and not of theme, the three key figures are the Magdalene at the center; the cross i t s e l f , which occupies the upper quadrant of the picture and dominates the action below; and the old man; i f the twisting movement of the composition has i t s vortex in the cross i t s e l f , i t i s the figure of the old man which serves to unify the upper and lower figure groups by offsetting the twisting motion of the cross and returning the eye to the foreground.  This i s a l l the more apparent i f we imagine the cross  facing i n the same direction as the old man, i n which case the ent i r e complicated structure begins to lose focus.  There i s no stagey  stiffness i n Pierre's work, but rather a circular turbulence which underlies the physical and emotional atmosphere of the moment. So i f Pierre borrowed from Carracci, he certainly improved upon his find, not because complicated structure i s superior, necessarily, to simple structure, but because i n painting, thematic content i s preferable to theatrics. I f structural analysis suggests an exercise i n geometry rather than the creation of a work of art, i t must be borne i n mind that artists i n a l l periods have recognized the importance of mathematical values and relationships i n building up their compositional patterns, from the two-dimensional universe of the Byzantine icons, to Leonardo's pyramid, Titian's right triangle, Raphael's ellipse and Poussin's stately diagonals.  When Diderot discusses composition,  he seems to understand the term to refer sometimes to subject matter or content, sometimes to the arrangement of the figures; he does not relate these elements to structure, however, so much as he does to ideology; as a result, he i s not concerned with how a painting i s put together, but with what i t says, which i s fine, but lacking any  structural or technical principle on which to base judgment, i t i s much easier to "mis-read" that statement.  Far from being an exer-  cise i n geometry, a familiarity with some of the properties of composition enables one to see that much deeper into the painting before him and, most importantly, to comprehend i t i n the idiom of the artist.  Of course, composition i s thematic as well as struc-  tural, and—as can be seen from the comparison between Carracci and Pierre—good form does not necessarily presuppose good content. Diderot's discussion of Vien's work i n the Salon of I763 provides an interesting contrast between traditional religious and neo-classical art; i t also provides a telling i l l u s t r a t i o n of the appeal that neo-classical art held for the educated eighteenth-century man.  In his opening remarks, Diderot writes that i t i s so  d i f f i c u l t to produce something even mediocre, and yet so easy to sense that mediocrity, and that this i s the role of the c r i t i c , but fortunately, Diderot sees i n Vien a painter whom he can praise a l most without reserve, whose painting? have elegance, grace, innocence, delicacy, s i m p l i c i t y — a l l joined to a purity of design, truthful color and l i f e l i k e flesh.  Diderot i s , of course, strongly  attracted to the subject matter provided by Antiquity, or what were--more accurately—renderings of Antiquity grounded i n the contemporary imagination. Vien's extremely bad "Wardrobe Dealer" rot as possessing the following qualities:  (Fig. 5)  strikes Dide-  i n f i n i t e intelligence,  elegance, tranquility, finesse, and exquisite accessories; nothing i s comparable for lightness of touch, and the background well characterizes the location of the scene.^  Alas, except for the fact  that the scene and contents are too s t i f f and cold to melt, this  could be a snapshot from the wax museum. The flowers, incense, and masonry are more suggestive of the mausoleum than of the ancient hearth.  The only thing of interest i s the gesture of the cupid,  and Diderot suggests that the standing woman i s , i n tucking up her toga, returning the salute. She i s also, i t should be noted, showing off the classical drape of her garment, an element which i s essential to any painting with classical pretensions whose only other noteworthy quality i s that i t i s monumentally inert. Yet Diderot sees i n i t a work of delicacy and "infinite taste". Were he to judge i t by his other set of standards—based upon nature as the model—he would have to condemn i t .  Characteristically i n -  consistent, he writes, i n 17&7: Reformer l a nature sur 1'antique, c'est suivre l a route inverse des Anciens qui n'en avoient point; c'est toujours travailler d'apres une copied But having paid l i p service to nature, he turns around and pays homage to many more mythological productions before the Salons end. Vien's work was outstanding, however, as an example of the neo-classical trend i n eighteenth-century a r t i s t i c thought, with i t s meticulous attention to archaeologically-accurate detail, as well as, of course, i t s conscious "imitation of the Ancients", which had perforce to be grounded i n imagination; as such, i t i s an exemplary neo-classical production—a cross between fantasy and the classicism of academic formula.  While i t may strike us today as being  calculated and inert, i t earned a place of favor i n the hearts of men like Diderot, not because i t had anything to say, but because i t was a l i t t l e piece of antiquity-revisited.  Although i t was with  reference to oratory that he wrote, Diderot's xrords—that the mind,  occupied with given and imaginary objects, w i l l always lack f i r e , warmth, and depth, and only rhetoric would remain-^—-might be applied with equal justice to characterize the neo-classicism of his day. Art was reflective, i n Diderot's time, of the coexistence of several currents of thought:  the rococo, with i t s f r i v o l i t y and the  neo-classical with i t s intellectual seriousness, both provided— through wish-fulfillment and authentic reconstruction of antiquity— a means of escape from contemporary l i f e .  But there was also the  cult of Nature, the simple l i f e , the common man and concurrently— with a declining philosophical credence in r e l i g i o n — a renewed emphasis on morality.  Genre painting—scenes of daily life—appeared  in the Salons as early as 1737» but,gained wider popular acceptance with the passing decades.  Both i t s origin and i t s popularity were  due i n part to a certain moral indignation toward the f r i v o l i t y and excesses of the aristocracy and partly to the fact that these paintings represented the artists' particular way of looking at the world. Greuze's work partakes largely of the former category—that of reaction against the rococo—although he had begun his career as a rococo painter. He turned to genre painting with a magic combination of didactic pretense and sentimental expression; Chardin impersonated the latter attitude, because his painting did not derive so much from philosophical persuasion as from temperament:  he was a  bourgeois, and the world he painted was his own world, comprehended and rendered i n his own particular way.  Yet for a l l his apparent  love of simplicity and common goodness--as a study of his work w i l l reveal—he neither preached nor patronized, and i n letting his subject matter speak for i t s e l f , he established himself as a master of  eloquent  understatement.  Then there i s Greuze, master of overstatement and folksy anecdote.  He was not only the most popular artist of his day; he was  also, characteristically, the worst.  He catches Diderot's eye i n  I76I with "The Paralytic", which Diderot immediately appreciates as being a "tableau de moeurs". rare beauty."-^  "The head of the paralytic i s of a  (So rare, i n fact, that Greuze must use the same  head i n at least a half-dozen more paintings.) In the recapitulation of the Salon of 1761,  Diderot discusses  at length another painting by Greuze, the most popular painting of the Salon, entitled "The Father who has just paid the dowry of his Daughter".  (Fig. 6)  Apparently believing that one picture i s worth  a thousand words, Diderot proceeds to turn the scene over i n print, providing dialogue, and even offering a manly wager that the fiance'e (the daughter) owes her forward look to Mother Nature and not to any coalition of elastic straps. The scene, he says, i s beautiful, just as i t must have happened, and he t e l l s us that the old man i s saying to his future son-in-law:  "Jeanette i s sweet and good; she w i l l  make you happy; see that you do the same for her."^  In an apparent  effort to extract as much domestic pulp as possible from this situation, Greuze has pulled out a l l the props:  the chicks on the floor  i n the foreground act as a counterpoint to the tear-stained mother and her brood:  one chick has l e f t i t s mother, brothers, and sisters,  and i s sitting on the saucer.  Once again, Greuze seems to summon up  for Diderot a l l the old theatrical associations, because he does not see the figures i n the painting as units of a structural or thematic composition, but as actors i n a drama.  Theatrical effect does not,  for this reason, seem inappropriate to him i n a painting.  In I763, Diderot looks at another Greuze confection, " F i l i a l Piety", (Fig. 7)  and declares:  C'est vraiment l a mon homme que ce Greuze . . .D'abord ce genre me plait; c'est l a peinture morale. Quoi doncl le pinceau n ' a - t - i l pas 6t6 assez et trop longtemps consacre' & l a de"bauche et au vice? Ne devons-nous pas etre satisfait de l e voir concourir enfin avec l a poesie dramatique a nous toucher, a nous-instruire, a nous corriger, et a nous inviter a. l a vertu?-^ The same white-haired old man,  too venerable for words, i s the cen-  ter of this picture; every other figure inclines toward him.  Dide-  rot mentions that the sheet hung up to dry which forms the backdrop, i s a good stroke, suited both to the subject" of the painting and to i t s general effect.  And indeed, the sheet which hangs diagonally  behind the figures exemplifies Greuze's expert use of structural devices to suit his compositional purposes.  The son-in-law, the  daughter, and the poor old faithful wife, a l l strain attentively i n the direction of the old man,  and their bodies form parallel  accents to the major diagonal of the sheet above them, but the effect of the regularity of these parallels i s — n o t surprisingly— stiff.  The attitudes of their bodies and the direction of their  glances carry the eye to the old man who reclines before them i n f r a i l incapacity. Greuze has further emphasized his central—and obviously, most beloved—figure, i n his use of light gradation: he has a pale complexion, white hair as luminous as a halo, and rests against a light-colored bolster; a l l the other figures are modeled i n darker tones, even the sheet—that peasant touch par excellence—that hangs above them a l l .  The old man obviously  receives a l l this attention and adoration with beatific gratitude. Greuze"s folk epic would not be complete, however, without that  breath of the barnyard that i s his signature.  In the dowry epi-  sode, the hen and chicks f i l l e d the b i l l ; i n " F i l i a l Piety", the delegate from the animal kingdom i s a mother dog who gives suck in the foreground as an apparent obbligato to the steady drip, drip, drip of the milk of human kindness. During the Salon of I767, Diderot remarks that . . .avec du genie i l est presque impossible de faire un bon tableau d'apres une situation romanesque, ou mgme une scene dramatique; ces modeles ne sont pas assez voisins de nature: l e tableau devient une imitation d'imitation.37 Significantly, however, he does not think of Greuze's work in this context at a l l .  To Diderot, Greuze's staged sermonettes are neither  f i c t i t i o u s situations nor dramatic scenes, but l i f e i t s e l f , and with moral lessons thrown i n . He never loses his taste for Greuze, and his  taste for the sentimental i s faithfully summed up in his c r i t i -  c a l — o r uncritical—ecstasies over "Girl Mourning her Dead Bird", in the Salon of I765. La j o l i e ele'gie! l e j o l i poemel l a belle idylle . ... Tableau delicieuxl le plus agreable et peut-etre l e plus interessant du Salon. Elle est de face; sa t@te est appuy€e sur sa main gauche: ..l'oiseau mort'est pose" sur l e bord sup^rieur de l a cage, l a te"te pendante, les ailes tralnantes, les pattes en l ' a i r . 38 Diderot proceeds to apostrophize the g i r l and carry on an imaginary conversation with her regarding her tears, love l i f e , etc.  So a l -  though he may sometimes disapprove of literary anecdote and mawkish theatricality i n painting, i t i s precisely those qualities which he admires i n Greuze—not as literary, but as instructive; not as mawkish,  but as sweet and moral.  Greuze chastises Ingratitude ("The '.  Punished Son") and pictorially extolls generosity, industry, charity, gratitude, and faith, but the personification of any vice or virtue i s a d i f f i c u l t thing to manage without the aid and consequent destructiveness of exaggeration.  In his choice of subject matter and  ambiance, Greuze shows a loving partiality to his peasant characters, but characters they remain, and one i s l e f t to wonder how much Greuze knew or understood about real people; i n trying to make his characters represent admirable qualities, he has abused the tolerances of a mute medium by substituting histrionics for humanity. Certain similarities i n subject matter i n Greuze and Chardin merely serve to emphasize the differences i n their expressive content:  In contrast to the staged incidents i n Greuze's painting,  those of Chardin appear as plausible events—not staged but observed —and with humor and sympathy.  For Chardin, nature—or l i f e — i s  people and things as they occur—ordinary and commonplace things which he sees and portrays i n a special way.  His works contain a l l  the dignity and simplicity that Greuze tried i n vain to convey; i f Chardin succeeded where Greuze failed, i t i s because he speaks the proper language of the painter—through light, color, and form instead of borrowing the language of the stage. The virtue that Diderot sees i n Chardin's s t i l l - l i f e s i s that they are so l i f e l i k e , they do not look painted. In the Salon of 1759, he sums up Chardin's work i n two words:  "nature" and "truth",  adding that one day his paintings would be sought-after. Diderot's consistent emphasis on "nature" and "truth" indicate that i t i s the pictorial f i d e l i t y to natural occurrence i n Chardin's work, rather than i t s thematic content, that arouses his admiration.  For this  reason, perhaps," Diderot consistently neglects Chardin's people i n  favor of his s t i l l - l i f e subjects. One notable example i n the Salon of 1759 i s his very passing mention, without further elaboration on any of them, of several of Chardin's works, among them a masterpiece, "The Young Artist".  (Fig. 8)  II y a de Chardin un retour de chasse; des pieces de gibier; un jeune eldve qui dessine vu par le dos; une f i l l e qui fait de l a tapisserie; deux petits tableaux de fruits; c'est toujours l a nature et l a veritg. ^ The f i r s t most striking aspect of the painting i s i t s texture: the surface i s extremely coarse, as though painted on an underlayer of thick impasto, giving i t a resemblance to rough plaster, and i t i s against this uncomfortable surface that.Chardin projects his young artist.  Sitting flat on the floor, his legs stretched out before  him, his sketch book i n his lap, he leans forward, his head bent down, and sketches.  His inclined position forms the diagonal angle  that i s the key to this composition and that leads directly away from the picture plane and into the heart of the composition i t s e l f . This diagonal, reinforced by the parallel accent of the portfolio he holds against his knees, leads the eye through the folds of his coat i n the extreme foreground directly to the sketch on the wall i n the background.  The attitude of the figure i n the sketch, and  especially the knee, the l e f t elbow, and the direction of the gaze, direct the attention of the observer to the third important element of the composition—the empty, xvaiting canvas on the right, whose major function i s thematic, rather than structural. Another thematic or psychological focus i s the young man's coat, which bears a l l the signs of neglect, including a hole near the .. sleeve; that the artist considered this element to be important to  his theme i s indicated by his placement of i t directly i n the onlooker's line of sight between the extreme foreground and the sketch on the wall.  Chardin has created a character study without showing  the physical or f a c i a l characteristics of the young man;  his per-  sonal qualities must be inferred from the objects with i^hich he surrounds himself.  The torn coat i s an image of self-sacrifice and  self-neglect, which i s further accentuated by the coarse surface texture of the canvas.  His character qualities are reflected, then,  i n the negligence of his dress, the attitude of his body, and his concentration and absorption i n the work at hand, which i s an experience of the imagination rather than of the flesh. Past, present, and future are indicated pictorially by the stages i n the process of. a r t i s t i c creation: (2)  ( 1 ) the model sketch,  the sketch underway, and ( 3 ) the waiting, empty canvas; yet  only one action i s taking place.  Chardin has painted a picture of  a young man drawing a picture of a picture, which indicates an empathetic point of view on the part of the artist, and infuses the work with both depth and lightness; and most importantly, he has amply depicted the qualities of patience and industry without the use of agonistic gesture and expression.  If, for Chardin, Nature  i s people and things as they occur, i t i s not for him the model from which he attempts to reconstruct the false idealism of personification; rather, i t i s the source of the ample reality of commonplace people and things whose uncommon qualities he  expresses  through textures, colors, and the nature of their activities, to portray the best of what l i e s deepest i n them, and at the same time to suspend them i n a monumental quietude. In  I76I,  Diderot says of Chardin that he i s always a faithful  (At  imitator of nature, i n his own rough and abrupt style; but that he depicts a lowly form of Nature—common and domestic.^  This idea  does not occur to him with regard to Greuze's work because Greuze depicts explicit moral lessons; Chardin's implicit statements require more of the observer than passive recognition.  He goes on  to complain that Chardin has lately been neglectful of hands and feet and seems content to depict his thought i n "four strokes of the brush"o  Here lingers a b i t of the old academism, which held  that a l l should be polished and perfect; i t did not admit of individual style; nor, from time to time, does Diderot. In 17&3> upon seeing a s t i l l - l i f e , Diderot praises Chardin for being an excellent ho  colorist who understands the harmony of colors and reflections. He was to mention Chardin again i n I765 i n connection with color, in his "Essay on Painting": .. . .celui qui copiera d'apres Greuze sera gris et violttre; celui qui etudiera Chardin sera vrai. 3 While Greuze composed his rustic rhapsodies-in-puce, Chardin was able to achieve—even with widespread use of greens and browns—a b r i l l i a n t effect of color by juxtaposing, rather than blending, the hues, so that each functions at maximum intensity, i n the manner of a mosaic, and a l l are radiant, even when subdued. In I765, Diderot remarks that s t i l l - l i f e painting belongs to old men or to those born old; i t demanded only study and patience— no verve, l i t t l e genius, l i t t l e poetry, a great deal of technique and truth, and that was a l l .  As an observer, Diderot has seen no  more and no less than many people see i n a s t i l l - l i f e , but as a genre i t represents a special area of. activity for artists by  occupying that middle ground between conventional subject matter and abstraction, and i n eighteenth-century France, the s t i l l - l i f e represented a subtle evasion of the established rules of painting which specified acceptable genres and, to a certain extent, prescribed subject matter as well. S t i l l - l i f e arrangement i s partly intuitive, partly mathematical,  and partakes more of the qualities of tactile concentration  than of rational comment.  Chardin was the f i r s t artist to devote  himself exclusively to s t i l l - l i f e s (after 1750 u n t i l his death i n 1779)  as studies i n purely formal relationships of color, reflec-  tion, texture, and arrangement. ceptively simple:  Chardin s s t i l l - l i f e s are de1  displacement or re-arrangement of any single  object might upset a balance whose existence had been imperceptible at f i r s t , and would necessitate other changes to compensate for the disturbed relationships.  Regarding Chardin*s s t i l l - l i f e , Diderot  instructs his friend Grimm: Choisissez son site; disposez sur ce cite les objets comme je vais vous les indiquer, et soyez sur que vous aurez vu ses tableaux . . . i l s sont tous de l a m£me p e r f e c t i o n . ^ A revealing means of testing Diderot's formula i s to try to imagine Chardin's "Attributes of Music" from Diderot's description of i t : . . .une foule d'objets divers, distribue's de l a maniere l a plus naturelle et l a plus pittoresque. ^ The inadequacy of Diderot's oversimplified conclusion indicates that a re-examination of the premises should have been i n order, that there • i s more i n Chardin's s t i l l - l i f e s than "study, patience, and perfection". In a work that has become a standard i n art criticism, Roger Fry  aptly characterizes Diderot's reaction to Chardin's work: Diderot's theory of art was a purely literary one. He regarded painting as an expression of moral values, even of the inculcation of morals, and says that the only thing that matters i s that the figures should express the emotions and that these should be of an improving and salutary kind . . .He adds that i f the figures also comprise an harmonious group, he, for one, gets an additional pleasure, but that this i s of no real importance. What was such a c r i t i c to do i n front of a Chardin s t i l l - l i f e ? He was, i n fact, too sensitive to beauty not to recognize Chardin's quality and he takes refuge i n an alternative theory of truth, to nature, of mere imitation.^ 5  One might well conclude from this, therefore, that while Diderot appreciates the quality of Chardin's work, he does so for the wrong reasons, but i f he mistakes Chardin's insistence upon the pricelessness of commonplace things for a mere pictorial statement that there are no useless objects i n nature,^ Chardin has at least partially succeeded nonetheless.  Although Diderot failed to recognize i t s  potential, Chardin's work would have bridged the gulf that yawned between the ignorant man and the educated man:  The appeal of Char-  din's work lay not i n reason but in\intuition and communicated, somehow, to everyone: . . .ses compositions appellent indistinctement 1'ignorant et le connaisseur . . .On s'arre"te devant un Chardin comme d'instinct, comme un voyageur fatigue" de sa route va s'asseoir, sans presque s'en apercevoir, dans l'endroit qui l u i offre un siege de ver-^g dure, du silence, des eaux, de 1'ombre et du frais. Just as the "Lullaby" i s the most un-Brahmsian piece of music Brahms ever composed, so Fragonard's "Head of an Old Man"  (Fig. 9)  i s alien to a l l the other paintings of that artist, i n style, subject matter, and tone.  Ordinarily, his taste ran to the mythical,  the i d y l l i c , and the lucrative lace-and-cotton candy subjects so popular i n his time, beneath whose soft and dimpled exteriors there beat no heart at a l l .  Diderot had admired Fragonard's "Cor6sus and  Callirhoe" i n the Salon of I765, but i n I767, he sees his "Head of an Old Man" as a disappointing anti-climax to it—weak,  soft, yel-  lowish, and with no vigor: Ce v i e i l l a r d regarde au loin. Sa barbe est un peu monotone, point touche'e de verve; m§me reproche aux cheveux, quoiqu'on ait voulu l'e'viter. Couleur fade. Cou sec et raide. Monsieur Fragonard, quand on s'est f a i t un nom, i l faut avoir un peu plus d'amour-propre.^9 The "Head of an Old Man" i s , nonetheless, an excellent painting. His eyes are closed (not looking i n the distance) and his chin rests upon his chest.  The parallel, diagonals formed by the folds of his clothing  and by the angle of his beard accentuate the downward movement of his head; moreover, the very presence of the heard i s a key compositional element:  I f we imagine him without i t , his chin w i l l not seem to  touch his chest at a l l , thus disturbing the restful, contemplative motif.  His head bows from the base of the neck, so that i t does not  simply droop but i s actually thrust forward, a movement which preserves the inclination of the head from lethargy. The yellowish color Diderot refers to i n no way detracts from the whole, but complements instead the peaceful motif by illuminating i t i n a gentle, languorous way.  But a significant and pronounced turbulence coexists  with a l l the superficial calm.  Boldly-slashing brushstrokes define  the facial features and the hair, whose uncompromising dishevelment bespeaks a tempestuous nature.  Rather than f a l l i n g vertically down-  ward, moreover, his clothing seems instead to flow out before him  u n t i l i t becomes part of the circumference of the picture i t s e l f . This turbulent expression of serenity indicates that Fragonard's aim i s not so much to create a revealing portrait of an.actual person and personality, as i t i s to penetrate an abstraction:  proceed-  ing from the heroic motif of the profile image and from s t y l i s t i c suggestions of the subject's temperament, the indirect luminosity which has no source and yet infuses the entire composition, through the angularity of a downward movement which accentuates decline, and finally going beyond that to the very shape of the p i c t u r e — the circle—which serves as an almost protective benediction upon the aging man; the circle which suggests repose and at the same time, having neither beginning nor end, connotes eternity.  Autant d hommes, autant de jugements. 1  1  DIDEROT AS CRITIC  From the above examples, chosen from the several Salons which Diderot discussed, we can see illustrated the thesis that Diderot did not set out as a c r i t i c to understand the works of art before him i n terms of the language of the a r t i s t .  He brought other values with  him, values which conflicted as often with each other as they did with the art to which he applied them.  His treatment of the works  before him, therefore, was descriptive and judicial rather than analytical i n tone. But somewhere among the c r i t i c a l snorts and halleleujas there lay i n Diderot an awareness of the unattainability of i n f a l l i b l e judgment. Insofar as standards exist i n his c r i t i c a l thought, both his Salon commentaries and his essay on painting are a study i n perpetual motion.  In the f i n a l analysis, he judges according to his  predilections and his taste, which he himself has defined as a capricious thing.  Of his c r i t i c a l judgments he writes, i n his con-  cluding comments to the Salon of  I?63»  J'ai senti, et j ' a i dit comme je sentais. La seule partiality dont je ne me sois pas garanti, c'est celle qu'on a tout naturellement pour certains sujets ou pour certains f a i r e s . 2  C r i t i c a l modesty surfaces again during the same Salon i n the remark that while a painter might say to him that he was missing many of the beauties of the paintings, he would have to say that there are so many things that depend on technique, i t would be impossible to judge without having tried i t himself.^ Later, i n 1 ? 6 7 , he reflects on the d i f -  ficulty of achieving understanding between the creator and the c r i t i c : Rappelez-vous toutes les etudes, toutes les connaissances ne"cessaires a. un bon peintre, a un'peintre ne", et vous sentirez combien i l est d i f f i c i l e d'etre un bon juge, un juge'nS en.peinture. Diderot sees as further and conclusive proof of the ultimate nonexistence of i n f a l l i b l e judgment—his own or anyone else's—the public demonstrations of t a s t e — o r lack of i t — g o i n g on around him.  In 17&5»  for example, he espies—and describes at great length and i n glowing terms—three sketches, three "masterpieces", by Greuze.  After des-  cribing the second of them, he laments the mediocrity of public taste: Avec tout cela, l e gofrt est s i miserable, s i petit, que peut-@tre ces deux esquisses ne seront jamais peintes, et que s i elles sont peintes, Boucher aura plutot vendu cinquante de ses ind6centes et plates marionnettes, que Greuze ses deux sublimes tableaux. But Greuze had a public to please, as did Boucher, and the sketches i n question were before long painted as pictures, not because of any i n fluence on the part of Diderot, but because of the realities of supply and demand. Popular judgment, then, because i t i s bad, i s inimical to the perfection of art because i t serves to perpetuate mediocrity: . . . i l ne faut que se promener une fois au Sallon, et y ecouter les jugements divers qu'on y porte,' pour se convaincre qu'en ce genre comme en litterature, l e succSs, l e grand succes est assurd a" l a mecliocrite', l'heureuse meaiocrite qui met le spectateur et 1'artiste de commun niveau. D i f f i c u l t as i t may be for the theorist i n him to accept, the sad truth i s — a n d he has said i t elsewhere—that only a handful of men of taste w i l l appreciate masterpieces, while the stupid, ignorant, and vulgar w i l l merely glance at them.  Je m'6criais: 6 Vernetl 6 ChardinI 6 Casanove! 6 Lutherbourgl 6 Robert! travaillez k present, suez sang et eau, 6tudiez l a nature, dpuisez-vous de fatigue, faites des poSmes sublimes avec vos pinceaux, et pour qui? Pour une petite poign6e d'hommes de goQt qui vous admireront en silence, tandis que l e stupide, I'ignorant vulgaire, jettant a" peine un coup d'oeil sur vos chefs-d'oeuvre, i r a se ptmer, s'extasier devant une enseigne a bierre, un tableau de guinguette.? But for a l l the f i n a l i t y and disgust i n the tone of his comments, this disappointment does not cause hrm to reject his notion that art should instruct the people, nor does his insight into the outrageous co-existence of masterpieces and mediocrities prevent him from heaping scorn upon Fragonard's "Head of an Old Man" two pages later.  He i s ,  i n fact, as guilty of ignoring masterpieces as anyone else, but he has just cleared the f i r s t hurdle of the aspiring c r i t i c :  the r e a l i -  zation that a r t i s t i c merit and public/rarely coincide. As a c r i t i c , as a judge, Diderot knows the weakness of his position and preparation, but he feels, nonetheless, that technical knowledge can be acquired. He put i t this way i n the course of the f i r s t three Salons (1759-63): Voulez-vous faire des progres stirs dans l a connaissance s i d i f f i c i l e de technique de l'art? Promenezvous dans une galerie avec un artiste, et faites-vous expliquer et montrer sur l a toile 1'exemple des mots techniques; sans cela, vous n'aurez jamais que des notions confuses. He followed his own advice and learned from the artists, but the technical and creative principles with which he became familiar were never systematized i n his mind; he could not, therefore, approach painting from principle or theory based on the medium, and instead brought with him principles and theories of his own.  He once said  that "anyone who knov?s how to judge a poet can also judge a painter".  Unfortunately, he tended to judge the painter by the poet's rules, with the inevitable literary bias i n his approach:  In neo—-or  pseudo—classical paintings he sought illustrations of Homeric vignettes, of odes, and of the mythological hordes at work and play; his pragmatic side dictated a literary approach as well: that of exacting of a figurative medium the l i t e r a l functions of didacticism; but he missed the implicit statements of Chardin and f e l l heavily for the oratorical distortions of Greuze.  A know-  ledge of the principles of art—from the point of view of the artist and not the philosopher—would have brought with i t a knowledge of the limitations and potentialities erf painting as a mute medium, but for Diderot, the illustrational values transcended those of creativity and experience. No less important to the c r i t i c than a knowledge of the derivative rules of the medium i s a familiarity with trends and influences. Far from turning criticism into a purely academic pursuit, this c r i t i c a l orientation provides each work with a valid chronological and cultural context.  I t does not necessarily imply a teleological viewpoint, but  i t does imply an ability to distinguish another version of the same old thing from a work that i s actually expressive and original i n i t s choice and treatment of subject matter.  Often perceiving neither what  the artist was trying to do nor how he was doing i t , Diderot discussed and evaluated painting without the perspective that the c r i t i c a l i n sights proper to the genre would have given him.  His ignorance of  trends and influences fostered the lacuna that existed i n his thought between classical art and that of his own time; rather than seeing a succession of cultures, values, styles, and world views, he saw a juxtaposition of the ideal and i t s revival.  Greek painting did not  exist; Roman painting was fresco and at best, decoratively functional; Diderot's models for a r t i s t i c perfection, then, were not actual works of art from the Graeco-Roman past, but literary vapors from the classical pundits.  His ideal, therefore, was dubious both  as to existence and to merit; lacking this perspective, he failed to recognize that in subject matter and i n treatment, the re-appearance of this antique "ideal" i n eighteenth-century France, which tried only to recapture the classical look without assuming the point of view that produced i t , was less a revival than an exhumation. As neo-pagan, as moralist, and as cosmic theoretician, Diderot confronted the plastic arts with a curious hybrid of values; but hybridization implies synthesis, and i n his thought on art, this did not exist.  He neither acknowledged nor applied a universal prin-  ciple, but saw art through the revolving, perpetual-motion  focus of  the cosmic theorist and the polarized distortion and discontinuity of the neo-pagan who could not synthesize ethics and aesthetics. Diderot knew that i t i s often easier to create a work of art than i t is to understand both the mechanics and the meaning of what has been created, and because he judges spontaneously, subjectively, and according to his taste, one tends to learn more about him, his prejudices, his way of seeing things, and his theories—however d i f f u s e — than about the paintings under study.  Diderot's success as a man of  letters i n compiling his "impressions" and his "failure" as a c r i t i c to elucidate the paintings  surveyed i n the idiom i n which they were  conceived, can be attributed i n large part to his personal conception of the function of the artist and from that, of the c r i t i c .  In look-  ing to art to supply l i t e r a l statements of intellectual and moral precepts, Diderot looked also to the artist whose hand would guide  the chisel or brush to supply that moral content.  In keeping.with  his notion of art as instruction, the moral lessons depicted had to be explicit; otherwise, they would be totally lost on the ignorant or the unfeeling. Although this was out of step with his concept of vague sublimity, etc., and although he was occasionally aware that mediocrity was almost always assured of popular success, nevertheless, he looked to the artist to conceive the idea, to depict the maxim, and thereby to sway the masses.  Impractical, impossible—yes—but  important, nonetheless, i n his concept of himself as c r i t i c :  He  exacted of painting the depiction of maxims and ideas, not i n the idiom of painting, but i n the idiom of literature and the stage— in allusion, i n gesture, and i n l i t e r a l statement; with the artist as illustrator of morality, with everything already explicit, there ought to have been—following that line of reasoning—no necessity for clarification or explanation at a l l . His theory—of the motivated artist and his moral art—rested, then, on a premise of v i s i b i l i t y and not of potential. Given his idea of the painter as instructor, i t becomes easy to understand why Diderot, as a c r i t i c , set out neither to interpret painting nor to understand i t but to judge i t — t o look, i n each painting, for an explicit moral, an idea. I f the idea or the moral were visible to him—and immediately s o — i t was a good painting; i f not, i t was bad.  There was no further meaning to consider. Diderot once  compared himself, as a c r i t i c , to a "beggar stirring i n the sand to find a flake of g o l d " ,  10  but without knowledge of the nature of the  terrain, he was dazzled instead by a l l that glittered.  Combien de motifs secrets et compliques dans notre bltme et nos eloges 1  DIDEROT'S VALUES AND THE EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY ETHOS  Fellows and Torrey credit Diderot with the creation of "moderft French art criticism as a literary genre" ; the truth of the statement i s undeniable, as far as i t goes, but/is interesting to note that they do not credit him simply with the creation of modern French art criticism, but go on to qualify that by saying that he created i t as a literary genre. Unfortunately, art criticism as a literary genre i s much like brain surgery as a literary genre:  quaint but useless.  To  attribute to Diderot, then, the creation of art criticism as a literary genre i s effectively to dismiss the substantial achievement that the Salon commentaries represent:  Diderot was not a c r i t i c i n the sense  that he spoke or even completely understood the language of the painter, but as a "philosophe" he was a c r i t i c of l i f e and of the times i n which he lived; this attitude framed his viewpoint i n looking at art, and i n the course of his commentaries, he recapitulated the vicissitudes of Enlightenment thought by bringing the current fashions, prejudices, ideas, and theories to bear on the art works before him. The Salons owe their longevity not only to bibliophiles—who would have preserved them anyway i n keeping with an innate reverence for dead things—but to their subjective nature as well.  This subjectivity makes  Diderot interesting as a writer but rather more d i f f i c u l t to deal with as a thinker and c r i t i c :  Partly as a consequence of a certain vola-  t i l i t y i n his temperament, partly because of the informality of his purpose i n writing both the "Essay" and the Salon commentaries, and also because of certain dianoetic impossibilities i n his thought, Diderot's  opinions on art appear as an ever-shifting series of inconsistencies, contradictions, and aesthetic and ideological incompatibilities which cannot be reconciled, even i n retrospect, simply by deciding that one view was the real one.  But i t i s precisely this quality i n him that  makes Diderot a representative man of his time, a true Enlightenment mind, where conflict and contradiction are fundamental to the ethos: The period of time approximately spanned by the Salons was one of transition from a stately classicism to a light-hearted rococo and a return to Spartan severity, from the decline of authority to the ascendancy of free inquiry, from belief i n God to belief i n man; and insofar as i t was a time where ideas collided headlong with ideas i n a dynamic, combative atmosphere of debate without resolution and confrontation without issue, Diderot embodied i t and French art reflected i t i n the themes that i t depicted. Diderot participated i n the l i f e of his time to the extent that he wanted very much to see changes done i n i t ; his attitude tovjard societyr i t s needs and faults, conditioned his approach to art; the Salons represent, therefore, the convergence of his values with the l i f e of his time as reflected i n i t s art.  As illustration of this point, the Salon of I767 deserves special consideration apart from the other Salons and from Diderot's other writings on art for at least three reasons:  ( 1 ) The Salon of 17&7  represents Diderot's maturity as a c r i t i c ; between  1759  and  17&5»  ne  wrote extraneously, never assembling i n one place the principles he actually invoked i n the course of the critiques, but following the Salon of I765, he wrote the "Essay on Painting" which did represent such a compilation of principles; the Salon of I767 offered him the  f i r s t opportunity after the formulation of these principles actually to apply them. Besides following chronologically the "Essay on Painting",  the Salon of  an art c r i t i c :  I767  represents Diderot's last and greatest effort as  It i s the longest and most thorough of a l l the Salon  reviews, and after 17&7 the Encyclop^die and i l l health diverted much of his energy and attention.  (2)  The 3alons have one advantage over  the Encycloogdie i n serving as a reflection i n detail of the spirit of the age:  Politics and religion were warmly-debated issues and  Encyclopedia articles dealing with these topics were heavily censored, and references to them were concealed, where they were included at a l l , under less combustible headings.  The Salons,"on the other hand, were  sent out of the country to Germany, beyond the reach of the censors' authority and were not published i n France u n t i l the nineteenth century.  Diderot knew i n writing the Salons that he could speak his mind  with impunity; such was not always the case with the Encycloogdie. The two works are completely different, of course, i n what they set out to accomplish, but both reflect the spirit of the age; the important point to bear i n mind, however, i s that where censorship poses no immediate threat, there i s a minimum of distortion i n that reflection. That he does not intend to keep s t r i c t l y to the paths of art c r i t i cism, Diderot announces early, i n a reminder to Grimm that the writings are to be kept confidential; he l i s t s among his reasons: Dites que les preguggs nationaux n'etant pas plus respectes dans mes lignes que les mauvaises maniSres de peindre, les vices des grands que les defauts des ar-' tistes, les extravagances de l a societe que celles de l'Academie, i l y a de quoi perdre cent hommes plus e"paulds que moi.^ In this Salon, then, Diderot treats art and society simultaneously,  as they are and as they ought to be. Finally, (3)  the Salon of  I767 contains, i n Seznec's words, "the entire vocabulary of Romanticism"; i t contains lengthy paraphrases of Burke, whose ideas on the "sublime" strongly influenced Diderot's thought^, although he never named the author or the work. Burke furnished the elements, but Diderot applied them as c r i t e r i a not only i n judging some of the paintings i n the Salons, but i n setting a new direction for that art.  Le beau tableau, dira l e peintrel La pauvre chose, dira le litterateurI et i l s auront raison tous les deux 1  THE SALON OF I767  Concepts i n opposition formed the essence of the eighteenthcentury ethos:  there was the lingering quarrel between the Ancients  and the Moderns, the conflict between reason and intuition, a tension between the spiritual and the temporal, the sentimental and the sensuous, and a l l were closely connected with liberty and happiness, which i n the eighteenth century were both abstract ideals and pract i c a l material goals.  The quarrel between the Ancients and the  Moderns represented a challenge of traditional authority; the further challenge of religious authority asserted the right of the individual to seek truth for himself apart from revelation; i f truth could make man free, i t could also make him happy;  the practical  side of the abstraction of truth was knowledge, and with the progress of science and the accumulation of knowledge, man could not only create a better world, but could better his own lot therein. Diderot did not, of course, discuss these concepts i n abstraction, but their currency i s obvious i n the various viewpoints he assumes i n evaluating the paintings and i n the subject matter of his frequent digressions and "detached thoughts": Mais laissons-la l a peinture, mon ami, et faisons un peu de morale. 2  Je ne vous de'cris pas ce tableau, je n'en ai pas l e courage; j'aime mieux causer un moment avec vous des pre"juge's populaires dans les beaux-arts.3  "Popular prejudice" i n the fine arts was frequently synonymous with fashion; i n fact art and fashion were indivisible to such an extent that Diderot sometimes saw the only hope of improvement in complete obliteration of contemporary practices and a return to chaos, from which some progress toward perfection might be expected. II y a dans l'art comme dans l a soci£t£, les fausses grSces, l a minauderie, 1 •affe'terie, l e prSeieux, l ' i g noble, l a fausse dignitd ou l a morgue, l a fausse gravity ou l a pedanterie, l a fausse douleur, l a fausse piete . . Diderot reinforces the equation of falsity with fashionable society i n noting that artists who allow themselves to become slaves.to fashion condemn themselves to producing petty fabricated reflections of a petty society: • • .nos temps . . .trds corrompus ou plutSt tresmani^res . . .Precautionnons done nos artistes . . . contre . . .l'influence de nos petits usages, de nos petits moeurs, de nos petits mannequins nationaux.?  Accumulation of wealth was indistinguishable from the rest of mat e r i a l progress, but luxury impeded the perfection of painting by enslaving i t to fashion and to garish tastes: N'oubliez pas parmi les obstacles h l a perfection et a l a duree des beaux-arts, je ne dis pas l a richesse d'un peuple, mais ce luxe qui degrade les grands talents, en les assujetissant a de petits ouvrages, et les grands sujets en les recluisant a l a bambochade; et pour vous en convaincre, voyez l a Verity, l a Vertu, l a Justice, l a Religion ajuste'es par La Grene"e. pour le boudoir d'un financier." Perhaps the key word i n this passage—as i t applies both to art and to s o c i e t y — i s "ajuste'es : In the rococo style, the personifications 11  of truth, virtue, and justice were not treated as historical subjects or personnages but as voluptuous damsels masquerading, i n a sense, as spiritual entities.  They had been adjusted to suit the  new taste, and what had once formed the substance of monumental subject matter now was merely t i t i l l a t i n g .  Monumental painting  had suffered from neglect during the early years of the century because the source of patronage had shifted from the court to the city.  The workshops at Versailles were closed dovm, and neither  the Church nor the increasingly secular society offered i t s e l f as a dependable patron.  Artists were therefore compelled to do smaller  paintings which would appeal to the wealthy private patrons who fre7  quented the art exhibitions.  From the idea that luxury engenders  decadence i n art, Diderot turns to a consideration of the ideal model, which exists neither solely i n the imagination of the artist, nor i n the monuments and paintings of Rome, nor i n the countryside of provincial France.  This facet of Diderot's thought on art and i t s  sources presents i t s e l f as a hybrid of neo-classical and romantic values:  The ideal model of nature—"la belle nature"—did not exist  i n nature.  The everyday face of nature was a corrupted form of i t s  ideal counterpart, and i t f e l l to the artist to seek out and reproduce this "belle nature".  I f nature was corrupted, the degree of  distance that separated i t from the ideal state could be measured i n terms of the advancement of c i v i l i z a t i o n .  This desired model could  not be revived solely through the spontaneous imitation of the Ancients; i t becomes corrupt and i s lost, et . . .ne se retrouverait peut-etre chez un peuple que par l a retour & l'6tat de Barbarie; car c'est l a seule condition ou les hommes convaincus de leur ignorance puissent se resoudre a l a lenteur de leur  tatonnement; les autres restent mecliocres parce qu'ils naissent, pour ainsi dire, scavants.^ Thus, a r t i s t i c purity could not be achieved i n imitation, but i n a return to rudimentary nature.  I f man could somehow shed the learn-  ing and sophistication that culture had bequeathed to him, he would find himself returned to the source without the vitiating influence of any model other than nature.  Diderot characterizes creation from the  void, the unaided, spontaneous creation, as "tatonnement", a concept which explains for him the unexcelled greatness of Greek culture: Je pretens que l a raison principale pour laquelle les les arts n'ont pu dans aucune siecle, chez aucune nation atteindre au degr6 de perfection qu'ils ont eue chez les Grecs; c'est que c'est le seul endroit de l a terre ou i l s ont fete" soumis au tatonnement; c'est que, grSce aux modsles qu'ils nous ont laisses, nous n'avons jamais pu, comme eux, arriver successivement et lentement a l a beauty de ces modules.9 This return to a barbaric age constituted a sort of "sensory rejuvenation", because, as Starobinski points out, as  eighteenth-century  man wearied of seeking live sensations i n rapid succession, he turned toward the image of the greatness of the past where primitive worlds were lost paradises of energy and intensity.1°  Mais ce grand goQt est comme l e tranchant d'un rasoir . . .  1  PROGRESS AND REVERSION  It was an age of belief i n material progress, but with an equal and opposite belief i n the salvation of humanity through a reversion to the natural state.  Most people, who concerned themselves with  such considerations at a l l , belonged either to one persuasion or to the other.  Diderot walked between them and embraced them both.  Perhaps the past could not be equalled, but the present could certainly be improved.  Diderot reflects this attitude i n castigating  the artists who modeled their paintings exclusively on the works of the Ancients: Serviles et presque stupides imitateurs de ceux qui les ont precedes, i l s etudient l a nature comme parfaite, et non comme perfectible. 2  Modern artists had been rendered servile imitators i n looking to the Greeks as a source of perfection, rather than to nature as that source. But i t was a circular dilemma; nature had to be perfected, according to the eighteenth-century canon for art; nature rendered i n art was not to be common, imperfect nature, but " l a belle nature" of which, unfortunately for future originality, the Greeks had provided the f i r s t and most "perfect" interpretations.  I f the Greeks had not  existed to be copied, the moderns, obliged to confront "une nature difforme, imparfaite, viciee", would have had to arrive at an o r i ginal model by themselves, a model which would have belonged uniquely to them.  As i t was, the works of the Ancients remained as a perpetual  monument to their artists and assured, by their continuing existence as models, the mediocrity of a l l artists to come. But this was the reverse of the eighteenth-century idea of progress:  nature and society were perfectible, but only because they  had evolved from perfection into corruption; i t was the perfectly respectable alternative belief for the atheist who could not accept the Biblical account of the Garden of Eden.  Progress was possible  from the present, but the eighteenth-century man did not necessarily consider his society to be the pinnacle of a l l that had preceded i t . Diderot's concept of returning to barbarism of the type from which the Greeks had emerged to rise to such a r t i s t i c heights, i s neoclassical i n that he attributes perfection to the Greeks and sees history as a long decline from a superior state of things. At the same time, his concept i s also romantic insofar as he seeks perfection not i n copying what has already been perfected, but i n reversion, i n a flight from c i v i l i z a t i o n and society toward the purity and intensity of the beginning of things. Even though he believed i n progress, Diderot did not believe i t could continue indefinitely without the advent, at a certain point, of decadence; and he f e l t that contemporary art and society had reached such a point: On trouve les anciennes routes occupies par des modeles sublimes qu'on desespere d'egaler. On 6crit des poetiques; on imagine de nouveaux genres; on devient singulier, bizarre, manie're'; d'ou i l parait que l a maniere est un vice d'une societe polici6e, ou.le bon gout tend a l a ddcadence.3 One could believe i n progress while at the same time longing for a -reversion to the fundamentals, because even reversion represented a  form of progress.  Nevertheless, progress was inevitably cyclical be-  cause of the predictable consistency of human nature: A l'origine des societe's, on trouve les arts bruts, le discours barbare, les moeurs agrestes, mais ces choses tendent d'un mSme pas a l a perfection, jusqu'a ce que le grand gout naisse; mais ce grand gout est comme le tranchant d'un rasoir, sur lequel i l est d i f f i c i l e de se tenir. Bient6t, les moeurs se depravent; 1'empire de l a raison s'etend; . . . les arts se corrompent par le raffinement, Refined taste and a corresponding refinement i n the arts had done their damage. Perhaps refinement was most objectionable to Diderot because i t indicated a stasis; i t neither progressed toward something newer and better nor undercut the influence of the Ancients by looking at nature as though i t were new.  Instead i t preoccupied i t s e l f with  i t s e l f , creating endless variations of hackneyed classical themes, moving neither forward nor backward and producing only a stagnant a r t i s t i c flotsam.  • . .1'empire de l a raison s'etend REASON AND INTUITION  Diderot believed i n reason, i n the possibilities that i t s application held for the development of mankind and the improvement of his world; whereas applied reason i n the form of natural and social s c i ence would aid society, i t would prove to be inimical to art; the practices of the Academy were a perfect example of the deadly i n f l u ence of reason upon art: Si j'avais l a Raison a peindre, je l a montrerais arrachant les plumes a Pegase et les pliant aux allures de l'Academie. II n'est plus cet animal fougueux qui hennit, gratte l a terre du pied, se cabre et deploie ses grandes ailes, c'est une be*te de somme, l a monture de l'abbe Morellet, prototype de l a methode. La discipline militaire nalt quand i l n'y a plus de generaux; l a methode, quand i l n'y a plus de genie.  ....  With the growing importance of the individual personality i n art and letters, of personal feelings and personal expression, tending away from the general type toward the unique particular, method represented the aridity of the philosiphic s p i r i t which sought narrow, s t r i c t , and rigorous comparisons and when applied to art, tended inevitably to standardize, to impose the lowest common denominator. And vigorous art was as incompatible with a materialistic society as i t was with the philosophic s p i r i t : Le regne des images passe, a mesure que celui des choses s'etend. I I s'introduit par l a raison une exactitude, une precision, une methode, pardonnezraoi le mot, une sorte de pedanterie qui tue tout . . . II est incroyable le mal que cette monotone politesse f a i t a* l a poesie.3  But since society was materialistic and since the philosophic s p i r i t permeated i t , Diderot looked to the artists to reinvigorate the emotional aspect of art, since people did not habitually respond to the i r r e s i s t i b l e magnetism of cold logic.  People i n general found  logic to be eminently resistible, i n fact, so that i f one wanted to communicate to the masses, i t had to be not so much on a level which they would understand but to which they would respond; art was to be a function of the emotions and not of the intellect; and the artist, as custodian of moral and emotional values, would teach and inspire morality by the appeal of the subject matter of his paintings to the emotions of his audience* En un mot, l a peinture est-elle l'art de parler aux yeux seulement? ou celui de s'adresser au coeur et a l'esprit, de charmer l'un, d'e'mouvoir 1'autre, par l'entremise des yeux. 0 mon ami, . . . l a plate chose qu'un morceau de peinture bien f a i t , bien peint.^"  . . .les moeurs se depravent  1  MORALITY AND ANTIMORALITY  It was axiomatic with Diderot that i f art were to be improved, morality must improve; the axiom was reciprocal, and the operations of the two were indivisible.  This i s one reason for Diderot's im-  patience with Boucher, who at the time of the writing of the Salon of 176? was Director of the Academy. Diderot acknowledged that Boucher could have been the best among a l l the artists had he wanted to be; failing that, Boucher's themes and techniques merely confirmed Diderot's belief i n the i n d i v i s i b i l i t y of art and morality, and i n the fact that there was need for improvement i n bqth. Je ne sais que dire de cet homme-ci. La degradation du gout, de l a couleur, de l a composition, des caracteres, de 1'expression, du dessin, a suivi pas a pas l a depravation des moeurs.^ Poetry, of course, was the quality that Diderot f e l t to be characteristic of the uncorrupted society, where vigor and v i r i l i t y had not yet become ossified, quaint ornamentation of an effete c i v i lization.  Reason and refinement, then, went hand i n hand as adjuncts  of civilization, i n destroying this "poetry"—the same poetry which Diderot wished to see infused into contemporary art to make i t once more an effective means of communication rather than the mere manufacture of ornament: II y a dans l a poe'sie toujours un peu de mensonge; l'esprit philosophique nous habitue a* le discerner, et adieu I ' i l l u s i o n et 1'effet. II n'y a plus moyen de faire des contes £ nos gens. 2  Of an age characterized by a fascination with opposites, the polarity between reason and intuition was but one facet.  This  duality was, i n turn, closely connected—as Diderot indicates— with another problem:  that of telling stories, of communicating  to people through anecdote.  Philosophy and poetry, reason and intui-  tion continued to contend with each other i n a society which tended toward increasingly intricate refinement. I f the corruption of art and the philosophic spirit were undesirable by-products of the refinement of culture, they contributed to—and were characterized by—a degeneration of morals; hence the importance of the problem: "II n'y a plus moyen de faire des contes a nos gens." I f the country was divided between bored aristocrats and busy bourgeois, i t was also divided between the moral values of these two groups—between libertinism, which was both intellectual and antimoral, and the moral" virtues of modesty, fidelity, and productivity. There were defectors from both camps, of course, but i n general, the divisions remained, and Diderot, characteristically, partook of the values of both.  Rococo art was frankly libertine; genre paintings  reflected the values of the middle class; classical art was inbred, involuted, aloof, and irrelevant; but there was a significant current i n French a r t — a s well as i n Diderot's thought—which represented a respectable compromise between the sensuousness of the libertine code and the sentimentality characteristic of the bourgeois taste: Greuze me dit, je voudrais bien peindre une femme toute nue, sans blesser l a pudeur; et je l u i repons, faites le modele honn§te. Asseiez devant vous une jeune f i l l e toute nue; que sa pauvre depouille soit a terre a c8te" d'elle et indique l a misere; qu'elle ait l a tgte appuye"e sur une de ses mains; que'de ses yeux baisses deux larmes coulent le long de ses joues; que son  expression soit celle de 1'innocence, de l a pudeur et de l a modestie; que sa m£re soit a c6te d'elle; que de ses mains et d'une des mains de sa f i l l e , elle se couvre le visage; ou qu'elle se cache l e visage de ses mains, et que celle de sa f i l l e soit posee sur son §paule; que le \r§tement de cette mere annonce aussi 1'extreme indigence; et que 1'artiste, temoin de cette scene, attendri, touchy, laisse tomber sa palette ou son crayon. Et Greuze dit, je vois mon tableau.3 The subject was treated i n the Salon of I769 by Baudouin, Boucher's son-in-law and protege", which fact i n i t s e l f i s adequate commentary on the possibilities Diderot's suggested painting held for the furtherance of morality through art.  Just as Diderot's sensuous nature  conflicted with his reason and his fondness for virtue, so Boucher represented a threat to that virtue i n his application of art to the  illustration of mundane and sensuous themes.  So long as Diderot  maintained his urgent belief i n the need for "moral painting", Boucher continued to intrude where and when he was most unwanted: Cet homme ne prend le pinceau que pour me montrer des tetons et des fesses. Je suis bien aise^d'en voir; mais je ne veux pas qu'on me les montre. Diderot looked neither to the philosophes nor to the public to reinvigorate art but to the artists themselves, because while on the one hand he lumped contemporary artists together as "servile imitators", he cherished on the other an idealized notion of the artist as a man of genius, a lonely, melancholy figure whose l i f e was touched with poetry because he lived according to extremes and functioned according to instinct.  Diderot's artist was melancholy because he was an ex-  tremist, and extremism was ultimately incompatible with happiness: Oui, mon ami, j'ai bien peur que l'homme n'allat droit au malheur par l a voie qui conduit l'imitateur de Nature au sublime. Se jetter dans les extremes, voila l a re gle -  v  du poete, garder en tout un juste milieu, voila l a regie du bonheur . . .11 est d'experience que l a nature condamne au malheur celui a qui elle a ddparti le gdnie.3  This notion of the artist as a man of genius, a lonely, melancholy figure misunderstood by society but who pursues his ideal nevertheless, indicates the direction that Romantic thought was to take i n the following century.  Paradoxically, i n Diderot's thought,  i t was the man of genius, unhappy by definition, who must lead the ordinary man to happiness by "inspiring" i n him a love of moderation. But was such communication possible between the passionate man of genius and the insensate common herd: Quelle difference, m'ecriais-je, du g^nie et du sens commun, de l'homme tranquille et de l'homme passionnel  0  Not only do the two stations remain diametrically opposed but, as Diderot indicates in his appraisal of common sense and the things that go with i t , the man of feeling—whether he be artist or philosophe—would not, i n honesty, choose to exchange places with the pleaceful, simple man because, as he states, the things that go with that estate are antithetical to his conception of the attributes of "l'homme passionne": C'est qu'il faut d'abord avoir l e sens commun, avec lequel on a si peu ore's ce qu'il faut pour @tre un bon pere, un bon mari, un bon marchand, un bon homme, un mauvais orateur, un mauvais poete, un mauvais musicien, un mauvais peintre, un mauvais sculpteur, un plat amant.7 The man of feeling must eschew the plodding, the conventional precisely because such a man, by definition, functions by the intensity of his emotions, his imagination, and his instinct.  Diderot seems, moreover, to be advocating a kind of hypocrisy whereby the artist would lead one l i f e and advocate quite another. But Diderot never exalts deception; at odds here are not honesty and hypocrisy, but the romantic and the moralist:  the romantic i n him  preferred to leave the man of genius to his own moods and creations; the practical moralist was somewhat more strict, urging the artist to devote his labors to the morally-instructive and inspirational anecdote; the values underlying both attitudes were reflected in corresponding genres exhibited i n the Salons.  . . . E s t - i l hieroglyphique?  1  DISGUISE AND DISCOVERY  Diderot implies that common sense i s the bane of anyone who would be a great artist or a great lover; common sense, l i k e virtue, i s easily admired but possessed only with d i f f i c u l t y because, requiring discipline, both are constantly at odds with the temptations and gratifications of the flesh.  According to the bourgeois ethic, i t was  not  sufficient to look good; one must be good as well; appearances were not enough.  The more rigorous the ethic, the. more elaborate the  evasion, and in eighteenth-century France this evasion took the form of the double l i f e , a combined l i f e - s t y l e and sophisticated game that expressed i t s e l f i n the popularity of the mask, of theatrical disguises and dual identities, the social necessity of either having or being a mistress, and of the courtly practice of masquerading as peasantsfor-a-day. The necessary corollary of such a practice—both i n art and in l i f e — i s surprise, or discovery.  Diderot went to some lengths to up-  hold the bourgeois ethics of hard work, moral discipline, and u t i l i t y in painting; and rococo painters, for their part, adorned their figures with rustic garb, sprinkled their erotic posturings with burlap and straw, transfigured both eroticism and reality, and abstracted them to a universe of pure fantasy.  Erotic themes frequently centered around  an incident where two participants were either spied upon or discovered, depending, probably, on whether the discoverers were aspirants or spoilsports.  The following i s a detailed example of the treatment  of such a theme. Works which undertake to t e l l an edifying anecdote  require clarity, but the following example illustrates Diderot's insistence upon clarity of situation, not so much because such clarity would help the painting f u l f i l l i t s instructive potential as to f u l f i l l i t s erotic potential by minimizing confusion and speculation; and we can see from Diderot's remarks about "Une jeune f i l l e endormie, surprise par son Pere et sa Mere" that i f i t does not t e l l a clear story, i t does at least suggest one, combining t i t i l l a t i o n with a rustic setting. La jeune f i l l e est couch^e, sa gorge est d6couverte, elle a des couleurs, sa tete repose sur deux oreillers . . .11 parait que ses cuisses sont separSes; elle a le bras gauche dans l e l i t , et le bras droit sur l a couverture, qui se plisse beaucoup a l a separation des deux cuisses, et l a main pos6e ou l a couverture se plisse . . .A droite sur le devant, c'est un panier d'oeufs renverses et casses. Sur cette inscription "Une jeune f i l l e endormie, surprise par son Pere et sa M£re", on cherche des traces d'un amant qui s'6chappe et l'on n'en trouve point; on regarde 1'impression du pere et de l a mere pour en t i r e r queique indice et i l s h'en revelent rien. On s'arrete done sur l a f i l l e . Que fait-elle? Qu'a-t-elle fait? On n'en sait r i e n . 2  Seeing no clear indication of what i s actually going on i n the painting,  Diderot indulges i n the pleasant task of suggesting possibili-  ELle dort. Se repose-t-elle d'une fatigue voluptueuse? Cela se peut. Le pere et l a mere appell§s par quelques soupirs aussi involontaires qu'indiscrets, reconnaitraient-ils aux couleurs vives de leur f i l l e , au mouvement de sa gorge, au desordre de sa couche, a* l a mollesse d'un de ses bras, £ l a position de l'autre qu'il ne faut pas differer & l a marier? cela est vraisemblable. Ce panier d'oeufs renverses et cassis e s t - i l hi<§roglyphique? . . .Encore une fois l e pere et l a mere auraient-ils eu quelque suspicion de l a conduite de leur f i l l e ? Seraient-ils venus a dessein de l a surorendre avec un amant?3 ;  Diderot was apparently not the only visitor to the Salon for whom this  painting created problems of interpretation; the limits of speculation seemed to depend, i n fact, only upon the amount of time one had to devote to the subject: Reconnaltraient-ils au desordre de l a couche qu'ils etaient arrives trop tard? . . .Voila ce qui me vient £ 1'esprit, parce que je ne suis plus malin. Mais d'autres ont d'autres idees; tous ces p l i s , l'endroit o\l i l s se pressent ...Sh bien, ces plis, cet endroit, cette main? Apres? Sst-ce qu'une f i l l e de cet Sge-la n'est pas maitresse d'user dans son l i t de toutes ses lumieres secretes sans que ses parens doivent s'en i n quieter? ...Ce n'est done pas cela; qu'est-ce done? ...Voyez, Monsieur Le Prince, quand on est obscur combien on fait imaginer des sotises.4 Paintings such as this constituted a kind of'gentleman's agreement between the artist and the patron; what would have been forbidden in written form was quite acceptable and avidly sought after i n painted form. Whatever Le Prince's paintings may have lacked i n explicit statement, they more than compensated for i t i n suggestion, so that their erotic potential was not f u l f i l l e d by the observer's looking at the paintings but by his thinking about them.  The ele-  ment of surprise, although not explicitly depicted i n this peaceful scene i s nonetheless present i n the broken eggs which suggest a frantic scramble on someone's part and also serve, perhaps, a hieroglyphic function, as Diderot suggests:  unless the daughter custom-  a r i l y made her bed i n the pantry, there i s no other reasonable explanation for the presence of the eggs in her room. Such surprise, of course, was much more easily enjoyed vicariously, even though the pleasure i t suggested was of the flesh.  Thus i n painting, i f not i n  l i f e , the penalties of pleasure could be as enjoyable as the pleasure itself.  The c r i t i c and the connoisseur i n Diderot can be seen to contend with each other i n his description of a painting with a similar theme; Baudouin's "La Chaumiere": Au centre de l a t o i l e et du tableau, une v i e i l l e , le dos courbd, le visage allume' de colere, les poings sur les cote's, gourmandant sa f i l l e et endue sur une botte de paille qu'elle partage avec un jeune paysan, pauvre l i t que je troquerais bien pour le mien, car l a f i l l e est j o l i e . . .son Elegance jure avec le lieu et l a condition des personnages . . .tout ceci bien peint, mais tres-bien peint, n'est qu'un amas de contradictions, point de ve"rite\ point de vrai gotit.5  The painting appeals to Diderot i n the d e l e g a b i l i t y of i t s subject matter, but disappoints him i n those aspects which would stand i n contradiction to his intellectual moral sense. Surprise or discovery was merely one of the hazards of personal enjoyment and thus became a common theme i n the painters' repertoire, appearing i n conjunction with amourous escapades i n rustic, contemporary, or mythological settings.  Other paintings with similar t i t l e s i n the Salon of I769  bear out the continuing popularity of the theme of discovery of forbidden enjoyment; painted by La Grenee and destined for the King's bedroom were "Vulcain qui surprend Mars avec Venus"; "Psyche qui surprend 1'Amour endormi"; "Jupiter et Junon endormis par Morphee", the latter of which appeared i n I767.  In the same year, disguise and  discovery combined i n Mme Therbouche's "Jupiter metamorphose en Pan, qui  surprend Antiope endormie".  The names and places varied from  canvas to canvas but the activity remained the same; i t represented the  perfect compromise between participation and escape—enjoyment  with impunity.  Nous aimons le p l a i s i r en personne, et l a douleur en peinture.' THE SPIRITUAL AND THE TEMPORAL  But Diderot sought to inspire art to move i n a new direction, which constituted the major reason for his reaction against rococo although he often enjoyed i t personally.  The tension i n Diderot  between morality and antimorality was not only reflective of the conflict i n society between middle class and aristocratic values, but also of the dichotomy between neo-pagan and religious principl which characterized the increasingly secular  eighteenth-century  society, and which underlay Diderot's search for a vehicle of lay morality as well as a sybaritic disdain for the mortification of the flesh. He was fully aware at. the same time that i t was as useless to look to the fashionable painting to disappear overnight as i t was to attempt to suppress i t : Je sais que celui qui supprime un mauvais l i v r e ou qui detruit une statue voluptueuse, ressemble a un idiot qui craindrait de pisser dans un fleuve, de peur qu'un homme ne s'y noySt. Mais laissons-la 1'effet de ces productions sur les moeurs de l a nation, restreignonsle aux moeurs particuli^res. Better lessons would be conveyed by busts, statues, and portraits of men who had served their country well as counselors, as men of letters or the fine arts; but the rococo would never f u l f i l l this function; i t was fashionable, i t appealed to a certain taste, but the fact that i t also appealed to instinct assured i t s continued popularity.  Besides expressing i t s e l f i n favor of the anecdote, Diderot's reaction against the rococo also took form i n a fondness for neoclassical painting.  In mid-eighteenth-century France, reaction  against rococo painting was f a i r l y widespread; i n disapproving of the subject matter of rococo painting, Diderot reflected the growing influence of bourgeois values i n French society i n the second half of the century. Certainly most contemporary painting and sculpture failed to satisfy Diderot's emphasis on u t i l i t y , which was also one of the most honored values of the middle class.  Works of art which  idealized—or even disguised—the amourous escapades of a bored aristocracy were radically incongruous with the virtues of labor, discipline, and chastity cherished by the bourgeoisie.^  In Diderot's  Salon of I767, the urgency of the need for "useful" moral painting can be measured i n the intensified severity of his criticisms.  He  retains h i s fondness for flesh without relinquishing his allegiance to the Utopian principle that moral painting would evoke a moral society.  Se j e t t e r dans les extremes, voila l a rdgle du poete, garder en tout un juste milieu, voila l a regie du bonheurJ MELANCHOLY AND THE PURSUIT OF HAPPINESS  That such Utopian moral principles would even venture into print suggests a tenacious optimism; i t was matched, characteristically, by a tenacious pessimism, whereby one might pursue happiness i n f u l l knowledge and resignation that he would never find i t .  In  painting, the inevitable end of the search for happiness lay i n a state of melancholy. i t s retraction:  Every attainment of man was accompanied by  the Utopian i d y l l with i t s classical setting  yielded to the ravages of time, and r u i n s — j u s t ruins—appeared i n French painting; peaceful landscapes became violent seascapes where man's insignificance was silhouetted dramatically against the whirlwind and the tempest.  This was the poetry, the grandeur, the sub-  limity that Diderot sought i n painting; i t was not nature, nor was i t " l a b e l l e nature"; i t was the nature of violent and irrational extremes.  Such painting inspired Diderot to reverie and reflection,  (which i s what he expected a good painting to do); a seascape by Vernet prompts him to reflect: Au loin, des pgcheurs . . .chacun . . .suivant des routes contraires quoique pousse" par un m§me vent: image de l'homme et du bonheur, du philosophe et de l a verite". 2  But to begin at the beginning, the Utopian concept held that the world was perfectible, but this could not be so i f man were not also perfectible, and from that, the corollary of utopianism—that perfect societies could be f i l l e d with happy people, that i f a l l else tended  toward perfection so also did the lot of man: Tout etre tend a" son bonheur . . But i n what, exactly, did happiness consist? liberty become license?  And at what point did  The eighteenth century had a tendency, i n  i t s mores and folkways, to confuse happiness with pleasure; the pursuit of happiness was only another face of the flight from boredom, the search for novelty. At the same time, and tending—in appearance, at l e a s t — i n the opposite direction, was the flight from a r t i f i c i a l ity, back to nature, to something original, fundamental, and pure. 0 sauvages habitans des forets, hommes libres qui vivez encore dans l'etat de nature et que notre approche n'a point corrompus, que vous §tes heureux s i 1'habitude qui a f f a i b l i t toutes les .jouissances et qui rend les privations plus amdres, n'a point alt£re" l e bonheur de votre vie. The key word i s "1'habitude", the deadly, numbing companion to daily l i f e , to which only savages and libertines could be immune—savages, because i n the state of nature, a Utopian state, habit and boredom did not yet exist; libertines, because habit held no power over those who searched endlessly for novelty. I t would seem, from this, that society tended i n two opposite directions, but i n reality the two penchants—toward  nature and toward novelty—overlapped.  In a  moral climate where mundane values were supreme, where the frantic pursuit of novelty and pleasure was matched by a manifest dread of boredom and monotony, virtue became the novelty to be sought after and assumed a l l the exoticism of a savage i n his forest, because virtue was the proper attribute of the natural man; i t vanished with the corrupting influences of c i v i l i z a t i o n :  Si tout concourt 2 perfectionner, tout concourt i. corrompre.5 How could eighteenth-century man recapture the lost primordial innocence?  How could he, enmeshed i n the refinements and polite con-  trivances of urban society, become a man again?  In what i s perhaps  the darkest passage i n a l l the Salons, Diderot suggests that i t i s the province of art to restore the v i r i l i t y to an effeminate society. The sadness comes from the knowledge that even this restoration i s only make-believe: Encha'ine's dans 1'enceinte dtroite des v i l l e s par des occupations ennuyeuses et de tristes devoirs, s i nous ne pouvons retrouver dans les forSts notre premier asyle nous sacrifions une portion de notre opulence k appeler les for§ts autour de nos demeures; mais la: elles ont perdu sous l a main symmetrique de l'art leur silence, leur innocence, leur liberty, leur ma jests', leur repos. The wish to escape refinement and contrived symmetry, to be closer to nature, expressed i t s e l f i n the popularity of the jardin anglais, where the geometrical symmetry of arrangement which had typified the seventeenth-century jardin francais yielded to a more "natural" arrangement; but i t was s t i l l only an arrangement and could not f i n a l l y alleviate the fundamental sadness: La\ nous allons contrefaire un moment le role du sauvage, esclaves des usages, des passions, jouer l a pantomime de l'homme de Nature.7 But i f art could not transform reality, i t could at least aid i n the escape from i t : Dans 1'impossibility de nous l i v r e r aux fonctions et aux amusements de l a vie champStre, d'errer dans une campagne, de suivre un troupeau, d'habiter une chau-  raiere, nous invitons a" prix d'or et d'argent l e pinceau de Wouwermans, de Berghem ou de Vernet d nous retracer les moeurs et l'histoire de nos anciens aieux. Et les murs de nos somptueuses et maussades demeures se couvrent des images d'un bonheur que nous regrettons. The affluent rococo society consisted i n materiality, consuming things, reveling i n the pleasures of the senses and for want of escape or further variety consumed i t s e l f ; happiness was a nostalgic memory, an elusive phantasm that disintegrated at the touch of the cultured man and went away to dwell with the poor i n s p i r i t : . . .Nous sommes devore's par 1'ambition, l a haine, l a jalousie et l'amour; et nous brulons de' l a soif de l'honneur et de l a richesse, au milieu des scenes cte.finnocence et de l a pauvrete, s ' i l est permis d'appeller pauvre celui a* qui tout appartient. Nous sommes des malheureux autour <desquels le bonheur est represent6 sous mille formes diverses.9 The unattainability of happiness may well have occasioned a genuinely heartfelt sense of loss on Diderot's part, but as a current idea, i t served also to direct one's preoccupation inward, where one could indulge i n the exquisite loneliness of melancholy.  Even pain  could be pleasant, but the sweet innocence of poverty remained sweet only so long as i t was unattainable.  No one really wanted to be poor;  participation i n the fashionable monodrama of melancholy demanded that one be comfortable and long to be poor, thus paying to the things of the s p i r i t the homage of hypocrisy.  In reality, the poor xrere miser-  able and dull; i n poetry, they were noble, the salt of the earth; i t was to this poetic, idealized notion of the poor that Diderot alluded when he referred to the "poor"; but as we have already seen,  10  when the  focus reverted to the melancholy, poetic man, "l'homme passionne'", the poor, common man suffered from the comparison:  6 bienheureux mortels, inertes, imbeciles, engourdis; vous buvez, vous mangez, vous dormez, vous v i e i l l i s s e z , et vous mourez sans avoir joui, sans avoir souffert, sans qu'aucune secousse ait fait osciller le poids qui vous pressait sur le sol ou vous gtes nds. On ne sait oil est l a sepulture de l'6nergique; l a votre est toujours sous vos pieds. Even though Diderot addresses them as "bienheureux mortels", neither he nor anyone else would voluntarily exchange places with them; i n fact, the very inconsequential!ty of their lives serves as illustration and justification of Diderot's stated belief: . . .garder en tout un juste milieu, voila" l a rdgle du bonheur . . . Happiness, like common sense and v i r t u e , ^ was not worth having; 1  happiness was dull; the pursuit was exciting, but attainment unthinkable.  Melancholy was erected as a barrier against the fortuitous en-  croachment of happiness:  melancholy could preserve the delicious  agony indefinitely, because the object of the pursuit, of the search, remained of necessity indeterminate: Quelquefois i l erre . . .saisissant tout, renoncant a tout . . The search centered perforce upon a vague object because once one determined what he wanted, there was a chance that he might find i t . The pursuit of happiness was one thing; the attainment of i t meant inertia.  Like the idealized poor, the noble savage of the forest,  the neo-classical pretensions to Antique grandeur, and the erotomania of the rococo, melancholy derived from fantasy; i t was not born of a saddening confrontation with reality but of a refusal to confront that reality; i n the poeticized state of melancholy, one could be  both an observer of l i f e and a participant, but never a victim.  One  assumed mental anguish as a defense against physical pain; loneliness as an alternative to overt (and unpoetic) rejection of the company of other men. Se jetter dans les extremes, voil& l a r<5gle du poete ... Rustic poverty, happiness, and melancholy were a l l extremes:  J  poverty  and happiness both represented extensions of middle-class values: poverty was the romanticized, idealized face of frugality; happiness was the exalted, perfected distortion of what was i n reality mere routine contentment.  Melancholy, with i t s vague searching and i t s  endless prolonging of emotion, derived from the "ennui" of the aristocracy.  Poverty was picturesque, but melancholy was a state of mind,.  and the perfect vehicle for incorporating melancholy into the visual arts was the depiction of scenes which would inspire nostalgia, reverie, and sadness.  The man of feeling saw i n nature a reflec-  tion of his moods and emotions—in whirlwind and tempest and brooding sky.  Paintings of nature where untamed, unyielding elements  seethed, smoldered, and exploded reflected this attitude and framed its  fantasies; but this Nature with i t s impenetrable passions was a  counterfeit, as the jardin anglais was a counterfeit, but calculated to s t i r the emotions, to move man to bethink himself of the shortness of time.  Paintings of ruins, the pictorial counterpart of oblivion,  also served this end and, since they depicted the aftermath of the ravages of time rather than the ravages themselves, they provided a framework for the projection of nostalgia and reverie.  Vernet's  brooding skies and churning surf and Robert's ruins brought melan-  choly into painting; the one by reflecting i t s moods; the other by inviting i t s celebration. Tending i n the opposite direction from the instructive anecdote, this a r t i s t i c current reverted to the principle of pleasure; and once again, i n keeping with that principle, suggestion was more evocative than explicit imagery: L obscurity ajoute a l a terreur . . .La nuit derobe les formes, donne de l'horreur aux bruits . . .met l'imagination en jeu, 1 imagination secoue vivement les entrailles; tout s'exageYe . . .La clart£ est bonne pour convaincre; elle ne vaut rien pour emouvoir. 1  1  1 6  The pleasure associated with such motifs derived from emotion and sensation rather than from the intellect: Monsieur Robert, vous ne savez pas encore pourquoi les ruines font tant de p l a i s i r , independemment de l a variete" des accidens qu'elles montrent . . . ' Whereas on the one hand, art portrayed nature as an embodiment of the passions, i t also served the taste for melancholy through overt imagery where ruins appeared as the emblem of vicissitude, and served an almost hieratic function i n purporting to evoke spec i f i c emotions through their very presence. Les ide'es que les ruines reveillent en moi sont grandes. Tout s'andantit, tout perit, tout passe, i l n'y a que le monde qui reste, i l n'y a que le temps qui dure. Qu'il est vieux, ce mondeI Je marche entre deux €ternite's. De quelque part que je jette les yeux, les objets qui m'entourent m'annoncent une f i n et me re"signent a* celle qui m'attend. 1  I f ruins represented the vicissitudes of time, they also represented a haven where one might wander i n imagination, experiencing terror  or languor, according to the suggestion of the image.  The celebration  of melancholy had an iconography proper to i t s e l f : Monsieur Robert, souvent on reste en admiration st 1'entree de vos ruines; faites ou qu'on s'en eloigne avec effroi, ou qu'on s'y promene avec plaisir.'° Ruins were emblematic and stirred the imagination because of the ideas one customarily associated with them: . . .Raison de- leur noblesse et de leur grandeur . . . I c i , i l se joint encore aux objets un cortege d'id^es accessoires et morales de l'energie de l a nature humaine, de l a puissance des peuples . . . Cela sembloit devoir etre eternel. Cependant cela se de"truit, cela passe, bientdt cela sera passd. 20  Paintings of ruins served their purpose i f they caused one to reflect upon the brevity of his span, but they also invited one to shed the petty annoyances of everyday l i f e , to assume the tragic passions of the daydream, and indulge i n vicarious emotional experience: Nous aimons, sans nous en douter, tout ce qui nous livre k nos penchants, nous secluit et excuse notre faiblesse. 21  But unlike rococo painting, which also dealt i n vicarious emotional experience, ruins represented the demise of society with a l l i t s a r t i f i c i a l i t i e s and vices and good intentions.  For the man  who  wished to flee those vices, the motif of the ruin appeared as the fulfillment of his wishes:  the l i f e of society became bearable as  long as one remained mindful that i t s i l l s were terminal. The motif of the ruin represented a l l these things to Diderot: Where monuments built by the titans of the earth to endure throughout eternity were destined to serve an uninterrupted succession of heirs  to their names, their t i t l e s , and their pageantry, Diderot saw an escape from daily l i f e , a solemn reminder of death, a place for the indulgence of daydream and melancholy, a stronghold of innocence, an altar for the celebration of remorse. II n'y a de leurs travaux.de leurs e"normes depenses, de leurs grandes vues que des debris qui servent d'asyle a l a partie l a plus indigente, l a plus malheureuse de l'espece humaine, plus utiles en mines qu'ils ne. le furent dans leur premiere splendeur. 1  Past grandeur fades and the poor i n s p i r i t inherit the earth, as Diderot turns from the attraction of the cult of melancholy to the concept of u t i l i t y .  While the art of his time presented many fas-  cinating diversions for Diderot, his concept of u t i l i t y i s never totally engulfed, nor do i t s attendant values of modesty and d i s c i pline suffer from permanent neglect.  In a century characterized by  an aimless and self-perpetuating pursuit of pleasure, Diderot attempted to evoke an art which would give that pleasure a purpose. Society and i t s usages consisted i n a state of polite hypocrisy and cynical pretense, a society i n which Le grand homme n'est plus celui qui f a i t vrai, c'est celui qui sait l e mieux concilier l e mensonge avec l a verite"; . .jusqu'a ce qu'un philosophe poete depece l'hipogrife et tente de ramener ses contemporains a un meilleur gout. Eighteenth-century French society was a fabric of concepts i n opposition:  with man's need to progress, to overcome the problems  associated with earthly l i f e , there appeared a counter-current of reversion, expressing i t s e l f in the human need to cling to the earth. In the age of reason and belief i n a l l i t s potentialities, intuition was also prized as a creative instinct, which could only function  and bear f r u i t apart from the aridity of logic.  One group honored  morality; another fashioned a l i f e - s t y l e around antimorality.  Fantasy  vied with reality as discovery invariably betrayed disguise. The worlds of the flesh and of the s p i r i t were far apart, but i n an i n creasingly secular and decadent society, spiritual values were a l l the more urgently needed to the extent that they were flouted or scorned. The pursuit of happiness was doomed to end i n disappointment, because i n the never-ending search for novel emotional stimuli, the stasis of contentment seemed almost bovine when compared to the noble sentiment of melancholy. Diderot's thought revolves around a l l these polarities and oppositions as he examines the art of the Salons.  Critics who dismiss  his commentaries s t r i c t l y because of their inconsistencies, and those who patronize him by minimizing those inconsistencies do him equal injustice.  Inconsistency and contradiction formed the essence of  his world view: Le beau tableau, dira le peintre! La pauvre chose, dira le litterateur 1 et i l s auront raison tous les deux.^ It i s no accident that Diderot was a man of many dialogues, a form he turned to frequently i n discussing the art of his time, indicating his belief that there are at least two sides to every issue, each of them worthy of consideration.  SOURCES CONSULTED Artz, Frederick B. From the Renaissance to Romanticism, Trends i n Style i n Art, Literature, and Music, 1 3 0 0 - 1 8 3 0 . Chicago: University of Chicago Press. I962. Combination of relative brevity and width of scope tends toward generality; informative nonetheless. Bazin, Germain. The Loom of Art, trans., G r i f f i n . New York: Simon and Schuster.I962. An impressionistic, interpretive survey; useful for illustrations. Canaday, John. "The Intelligent Woman's Guide to Art". New York: Book-of-the-month Club. 1959• A pamphlet, a promotional sample for a series of home seminars on art. Ridiculous t i t l e suggests dilettantism, but i n fact i t is a very perceptive study of selected paintings with emphasis on composition. Coherence and urbanity more than compensate for occasional arbitrary judgments. Canaday was art editor and c r i t i c with New York Times. Cheney, Sheldon. A New World History of Art. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.I961.Snob's-eye view of world art from Neanderthal to Armageddon. Pretentious, "appreciative" metavocabulary. Fry, Roger. Characteristics of French Art. London: Chatto and Windus. 1932. Written i n the form of an essay; thoughtf u l c r i t i c a l insights and a coherence of thought and language that i s unusual i n works on the subject. Herrmann, Paul, ed. DenkmSler der Malerei des Altertums. Munich: Bruckmann. I 9 0 6 - I 9 3 4 . Illustrations of the frescoes of Pompeii and Herculaneum. A comprehensive collection. Holt, Elizabeth G. A Documentary History of Art. Garden City: Doubleday. 1956-58. Volumes I and II. Both volumes feature selections of writings by contemporaries about art from the eleventh through the eighteenth centuries. Janson, H. W. and Dora Hanson. The Picture History of Painting from Cave Painting to Modern Times. New York: Harry N. Abrams. 1957* A general survey. Well-illustrated.  9.  Kielty, Bemardine. Masters of Painting, Their Works, Their Lives, Their Times. Garden City: Doubleday. 1964. Competent survey of selected artists.  10.  Leith, James A. The Idea of Art as Propaganda i n France 17501799» Toronto: University of Toronto Press. I965. Very interesting study, but Leith minimizes Diderot's sensuous side and the contradictory nature of his writings i n order to show him as a primary exponent of art as propaganda.  11.  Leppmann, Wolfgang. Winckelmann. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Only.recent biography of Winckelmann; objective.  12.  May, Gita. "Diderot and Burke: a study i n aesthetic affinity", PMLA. i960. Extent of Diderot's indebtedness to Burke, especially i n Salon of•1?6?.  13*  M^lbjerg, Hans. Aspects de 1'esthetique de Diderot. K0benhavn: Forlag. I 9 6 4 . T r i e s to arrange Diderot's aesthetic thought according to a framework, the "trinity", i n Le Neveu de Rameau. A thesis.  14.  Munro, Eleanor C. The Golden Encyclopedia of Art. New York: Golden Press. I96I. Alphabetically-organized information on artists and a r t i s t i c trends.  15.  Robb, David M. The Harper History of Painting, The Occidental Tradition. New York: Harper and Bros. 1951* Among the most scholarly and yet illuminating general studies of the history of painting. Robb i s a structural c r i t i c without being arbitrary. Extensive c r i t i c a l bibliography. Illustrations well-chosen but very poorly reproduced, almost none i n color.  16.  Rothenstein, Sir John, Gen. ed. consultant. New International Illustrated Encyclopedia of Art. New York: Greystone Press. I967. Illustrated glossary of artistic and architectural terms; cogent "period" articles.  17.  Starobinski, Jean. The Invention of Liberty 1700-1789. trans. Swift.. Geneva! Skira. I964. Purview of Eighteenthcentury England and France with illustrations from painting and architecture. Smooth, readable translation of a very illuminating study.  18.  Venturi, Lionello. History of Art Criticism, trans., Marriott. New York: Dutton. 1964. One of the few books available on the subject by a recognized scholar i n the f i e l d . Extensive bibliography. Occasionally d i f f i c u l t , abstract text. Translator writes i n English but seems to be thinking i n Italian.  19.  Welleck, Rend. A History of Modern Criticism: 1750-I950» Vol. I . The Later Eighteenth Century. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. 1955« Study flawed by imprecision of terms: uses art as catch-all for painting, poetry, and theater; uses "classicism" and "neo-classicism" interchangeably, which creates a falsification; not only are the two not interchangeable, but as literary and a r t i s t i c movements, they do not coincide either chronologically or substantially.  WORKS CITED  1.  Bazin, Germain. The Loom of Art, trans., G r i f f i n . Simon and Schuster, I962.  2.  Cheney, Sheldon. A New World History of Art. New York: Rinehart, and Winston, I961.  3.  Cicero.  4.  Diderot, Denis. "Essai sur l a Painture", i n Oeuvres Completes. Assezat, ed. P a r i s : Gamier, I876. V o l . X.  5»  ••  Rhetorica ad Herennium. mann, 1954.  .  Holt,  trans., Caplan. London:  Heine-  "Pensdes Detachers sur l a Peinture", i n Oeuvres Com-  pldtes.  6.  New York:  V o l . XII.  . Salons. Seznec et Adhemar, eds. Press, I963. Vols. I - I I I .  Oxford: Clarendon  7.  Fellows, Otis and Norman Torrey, eds. The Age of Enlightenment. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1942.  8.  Fry, Roger. C h a r a c t e r i s t i c s of French Art. London: Windus, 1932.  9.  Holt, Elizabeth Greene, ed. A Documentary History of Art. Gar. den C i t y : Doubleday, 1956. Vol. I .  10.  ;. A Documentary History of Art. Garden C i t y : day, 1958. Vol. I I .  11.  Leith, James A. The Idea of Art as Propaganda i n France 17501799. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, I965.  12.  May, G i t a . "Diderot and Burke: PICA, i960.  a study i n aesthetic  Chatto and  Double-  affinity".  13«  M^lbgerg, Hans. Aspects de 1'esthetique de Diderot. Forlag, 19oX.  14.  Saint-Yenne, de, La Font. Reflexions sur quelques causes de l'etat present de l a peinture en France. Paris, 1747 and 1752.  15.  Starobinski, Jean. The Invention of Liberty I70O-I789. Swift. Geneva! Skira, 1964.  16.  Tourneux, ed.  17.  Venturi, Lionello. History of Art Criticism, New York: Dutton, I964.  18.  Winckelmann, Johann. Gedanken uber die Nachamung der grieschischen Werke i n der Malerei und Bildhauericunst. Dresden u. Leipzig, 1755.  19.  Correspondance l i t t e r a i r e .  K^benhavn:  trans.  Paris, I878. trans., Marriott.  . Geschicte der Kunst des Altertums. Weimar: 176'4.  Bohlaus,  FOOTNOTES  INTRODUCTION 1.  Bazin, Germain, The Loom of Art, trans, J. Griffin, New York, Simon and Schuster, 1962, p. 123.  2.  Starobinski, Jean, The Invention of Liberty, 1700-1739» trans. Bernard C. Swift, Geneva, Skira, 1964, p. 10,  3«  ibid., p. 13*  DIDEROT IN THE SCHEME OF THINGS 1.  Venturi, Lionello, History of Art Criticism, trans. C. Marriott, New York,. Dutton, 1964, pp. 141-42.  2.  Saint-Yenne, La Font de, Reflexions sur quelques causes de l'gtat present de l a peinture en France, Paris, 1747 and  1752.  3.  Leith, James A. The Idea of Art as Propaganda i n France 17501799. Toronto, University of Toronto Press, 1965. P» 8.  4.  loc. c i t .  5.  Diderot, Denis, Salons, ed. Seznec et Adhemar, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1963, Vol. I l l , p. 154. Cheney, Sheldon, A New World History of Art, New York, Holt,  6.  Rinehart, and Winston, I96I, p. 516. 7.  see infra., p. •Vi.  8. 9.  see supra., pp. Winckelmann, Johann, Gedanken uber die Nachamung der grieschischen Werke i n der Malerei u. Bildhauerkunst, Dresden u. Leipzig,  1755. 10.  , Geschicte der Kunst des Altertums, Weimar, Bohlaus,  DIDEROT'S "AESTHETICS"AS KEY TO HIS CRITICISM ^ 1.  Venturi, History of Art Criticism, p. 136.  2.  M^lbjerg, Hans, Aspects de I'esthetique de Diderot, Ko'benhavn, Forlag, 1964, p. 11.  '  THE ESSAY ON PAINTING: SYNOPSIS THE ESSAY ON PAINTING:  1765  1.  Diderot, Denis, Oeuvres Compldtes, ed. J. Ass6sat, Paris, Garnier, I 8 7 6 , Vol. X., "Essai sur l a Peinture", p. 461.  2.  Cicero, Rhetorica ad Herennium, trans. Caplan, London, Heinemann, 1954,  pp. 2 2 0 - 2 1 .  3.  Diderot, Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai", p.. 4 6 8 .  4.  ibid. p. 470.  5.  ibid., passim.  6.  Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai", p. 486.  7.  Diderot, Salons, S. et A., Vol. I, p. 6 4 .  8.  Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai", p. 486.  9.  ibid., p. 485.  10.  ibid., p. 4 9 2 - 9 3 .  11.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 214.  12.  Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai", p. 503*  13.  Salons, Vol. I, p.. 214.  14. loc. c i t . 15.  Diderot, Denis, Oeuvres Completes, ed. Assezat, Paris, Garnier, I 8 7 6 , Vol. XII, "Pensdes Detachers sur l a Peinture", p. 84.  16.  ibid., p. 8 6 .  17.  Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai", p. 504.  18.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 205-  19.  Oeuvres, Vol. XII, p. 8 8 .  (THE ESSAY ON PAINTING:  I765)  20.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 123.  21.  Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai",. p. 518.  22.  ibid., p. 519.  23.  ibid,, p. 500.  24.  ibid., p. 501.  25.  Oeuvres, Vol. XII, "Pens6es Detachers", p. 75.  26.  Holt, Elizabeth G., ed., A Documentary History of Art, Garden City, Doubleday, 1958,  Vol. I, p. 277.  27.  Oeuvres, Vol. X, "Essai", p. 501  28.  ibid., p. 503.  29.  ibid., p. 506.  30.  ibid., p. 517.  31.  loc. c i t .  32. ibid., p. 519. 33.  Oeuvres, Vol. XII, "Pensdes", p. 125.  34.  ibid., Vol. X, "Essai", p. 520.  35.  ibid., p. 519.  36. 37.  ibid., Vol. XII, "Pensees',', p. 76. ibid., p. 131.  THE SALONS  1759-1781: DIDEROT'S TASTE AND METHOD  1.  Tourneux, ed. Correspondance l i t t e r a i r e , Paris, I878.  2.  see supra., p. 3f.  SELECTED COMMENTARIES  1.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 108.  (SELECTED COMMENTARIES) 3.  ibid., p. 249.  4. loc. c i t . 5«  loc. c i t .  6. loc. c i t . 7.  ibid., Vol. I I , p. 86.  8. ibid., p. 111. 9.  ibid.. Vol. I l l , p. 65.  10.  ibid., p. 71.  11.  ibid., p. 201.  12.  ibid., p. 280.  13.  ibid., Vol. I, p. 112.  14.  loc. c i t .  15.  ibid., Vol. II, p. 75-  16.  loc. c i t .  17.  Oeuvres, Vol. XII, "Pensees", p. 122.  18.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 69.  19.  ibid., p. 137.  20.  ibid., p. 146.  21.  ibid., p. 204.  22.  see supra, p. Z/.  23.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 136.  24.  ibid., p. 64.  25.  loc. c i t .  26.  loc. c i t .  27.  ibid., p. 108.  (SELECTED COMMENTARIES)  29.  loc. c i t .  30.  i b i d . , p. 113.  31.  i b i d . , p. 210.  32.  i b i d . , V o l . I l l , p. 67.  33.  i b i d . , V o l . I, p. 123.  34.  i b i d . , p. 135.  35.  i b i d . , p. 142.  36.  i b i d . , p. 233.  37.  i b i d . , V o l . I l l , p. 286.  38.  i b i d . , V o l . I I , p. 145.  39.  i b i d . , V o l . I, p. 66.  40.  loc. c i t .  41.  i b i d . , p. 125.  42.  i b i d . , p. 222.  43.  Oeuvres, V o l . X, p. 470.  44.  Salons, V o l . I I , p. 111.  45.  i b i d . , p. 112.  46.  Fry, Roger, C h a r a c t e r i s t i c s of French Art, London, Chatto and Windus, 1932, p. 66.  47.  Salons, V o l . I I , p. 113.  48.  i b i d . , V o l . I l l , p. 128-29.  49.  i b i d . , V o l . I l l , p. 280.  DIDEROT AS CRITIC 1.  Salons, V o l . I l l , p. 89  2.  i b i d . , V o l . I . p. 248.  (DIDEROT AS CRITIC) 4. ibid., Vol. I l l , p. 278. 5.  ibid., Vol. II, p. 159.  6.  ibid., Vol. I l l , p. 278.  7. loc. c i t . 8.  Oeuvres, Vol. XII, "Pensees", p. 113.  9.  Salons, Vol. I, p. 10.  10.  ibid., p. 209.  DIDEROT'S VALUES AND THE EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY ETHOS ' 1.  Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 70.  2.  Fellows, Otis S. and Norman L. Torrey, eds., The Age of Enlightenment, Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., New York, 1942, p. 2 8 8 .  3.  Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 64.  4.  see May, Gita, "Diderot and Burke:  a study i n aesthetic af-  finity", PMLA, Dec. i 9 6 0 , pp. 527-39* THE SALON OF I767 1.  Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 87.  2.  ibid., p. 69.  3.  ibid., p. 277.  4. ibid., "De l a maniere", p. 338. 5.  ibid., p. 238.  6.  ibid., p. 56.  7.  Leith, The Idea of Art as Propaganda i n France 1750-1799. p.  8.  Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 6 l .  9.  ibid., p. 63.  (THE SALON OF 1767) 10.  Starobinski, The Invention of Liberty 1700-1789, p. 188.  PROGRESS AND REVERSION Salons, Vol. I l l , "De l a maniere", p. 3 3 6 . 2.  ibid., p. 6l.  3. ibid., "De l a maniere", p. 3 3 6 . 4. loc. c i t . REASON MD INTUITION 1.  Salons, Vol. I l l , "De l a maniere", p. 3 3 6 .  2.  ibid., p. 1 5 4 .  3. ibid., p. 1 5 3 * 4. ibid., p. 1 1 7 . 5.  ibid., Vol. II, p. 7 5 '  MORALITY AND ANTIMORALITY 1.  Salons, Vol. I l l , "De l a manidre", p. 3 3 6 .  2.  ibid., p. 1 5 7 .  3. ibid., pp. 109-10. 4. ibid., Vol. II, p. 78. 5.  ibid., Vol. I l l , p. 148.  6.  ibid., p. 149.  7. ibid., p. 308. DISGUISE AND DISCOVERY 1.  Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 2 1 5 .  (DISGUISE AND DISCOVERY) 2. loc. c i t . 3. loc. c i t . 4.  loc. c i t .  5. ibid., p. 202. THE SPIRITUAL AND THE TEMPORAL 1. Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 144. 2. ibid., p. 199. 3. Leith, The Idea of Art as Propaganda i n France, p. ? passim. MELANCHOLY AND THE PURSUIT OF HAPPINESS 1. Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 148. 2. ibid., p. 146. 3. ibid., p. 148. 4. ibid., p. 152. 5. ibid., p. 238. 6.  ibid., p. 139'  7. loc. c i t . 8. loc. c i t .  9. loc. c i t . 10.  see supra., p. 91, nn. 6 and "7.  11.  ibid., p. 222.  12.  ibid., p. 148.  13.  see supra., p. 9/.  14.  Salons, Vol. I l l , p. 222.  (MELANCHOLY AND THE PURSUIT OF HAPPINESS) 16.  ibid., p. I65.  17.  ibid., p. 228.  18.  loc. c i t .  19.  ibid., p. 234.  20.  ibido, p. 118.  21.  ibid., p. 229.  22.  ibid;, p. 246.  23.  ibid., p. 248.  24.  ibid., p. 87.  ILLUSTRATIONS  6.  CARLK VAN  LOO.  7.  CARLK VAN  LOO.  Mcilcc  Baigneuscs  C a r l e Van Loo  "The Bathers" Figure 1  22. L-M. v . -  Lo... Lc Roi  L.-M. Van Loo P o r t r a i t of the King Figure 2  J.-B. Pierre "Descent from the Cross" Figure 3  Vien:  "The  Wardrobe D e a l e r "  Figure  5  Greuze:  "Father who has j u s t paid the dowry of h i s Figure 6  Greuze:  " F i l i a l Piety"  Figure 7  Fragonard:  "Head of an Old Man"  Figure 9  

Cite

Citation Scheme:

    

Usage Statistics

Country Views Downloads
United States 16 4
Brazil 9 0
China 9 23
France 7 0
Germany 5 4
Japan 3 0
Serbia 1 0
Nigeria 1 0
United Kingdom 1 2
Romania 1 0
City Views Downloads
Unknown 20 5
Beijing 9 0
Washington 6 0
Porto Alegre 5 0
Ashburn 4 0
Tokyo 3 0
Arlington Heights 2 0
Wilmington 1 0
Oxford 1 0
Boise 1 0
Dallas 1 0

{[{ mDataHeader[type] }]} {[{ month[type] }]} {[{ tData[type] }]}
Download Stats

Share

Embed

Customize your widget with the following options, then copy and paste the code below into the HTML of your page to embed this item in your website.
                        
                            <div id="ubcOpenCollectionsWidgetDisplay">
                            <script id="ubcOpenCollectionsWidget"
                            src="{[{embed.src}]}"
                            data-item="{[{embed.item}]}"
                            data-collection="{[{embed.collection}]}"
                            data-metadata="{[{embed.showMetadata}]}"
                            data-width="{[{embed.width}]}"
                            async >
                            </script>
                            </div>
                        
                    
IIIF logo Our image viewer uses the IIIF 2.0 standard. To load this item in other compatible viewers, use this url:
http://iiif.library.ubc.ca/presentation/dsp.831.1-0102179/manifest

Comment

Related Items